If the objects of a category form a proper class, do the arrows necessarily form a proper class too?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
2
down vote

favorite












In some categories, like $textSet$ or $textGroup$, the objects are "constructed" out of sets (or are sets, possibly with additional structure). In order to avoid paradoxes, the collection of objects is therefore a proper class✱.



If the class of objects is proper, is it possible for the collection of arrows to still be a set?



A not-convincing argument against it is that each object gets an identity arrow therefore there are "too many" arrows to be a set. I don't trust intuitions about size with things as big as $textSet$ though.



A not-convincing argument that it's plausible is that arrows are opaque and I, the category-maker, get to freely pick the labels for the arrows, the definition of the composition relation, and the source and destination for each of the arrow-labels. How do I show that I can't come up with a set of labels big enough to label all of my arrows?




✱ I don't know whether it makes sense to start with a "possibly-proper class of all sets satisfying some predicate" and then inspect the class in some way to see if it's a proper class or not.










share|cite|improve this question



























    up vote
    2
    down vote

    favorite












    In some categories, like $textSet$ or $textGroup$, the objects are "constructed" out of sets (or are sets, possibly with additional structure). In order to avoid paradoxes, the collection of objects is therefore a proper class✱.



    If the class of objects is proper, is it possible for the collection of arrows to still be a set?



    A not-convincing argument against it is that each object gets an identity arrow therefore there are "too many" arrows to be a set. I don't trust intuitions about size with things as big as $textSet$ though.



    A not-convincing argument that it's plausible is that arrows are opaque and I, the category-maker, get to freely pick the labels for the arrows, the definition of the composition relation, and the source and destination for each of the arrow-labels. How do I show that I can't come up with a set of labels big enough to label all of my arrows?




    ✱ I don't know whether it makes sense to start with a "possibly-proper class of all sets satisfying some predicate" and then inspect the class in some way to see if it's a proper class or not.










    share|cite|improve this question

























      up vote
      2
      down vote

      favorite









      up vote
      2
      down vote

      favorite











      In some categories, like $textSet$ or $textGroup$, the objects are "constructed" out of sets (or are sets, possibly with additional structure). In order to avoid paradoxes, the collection of objects is therefore a proper class✱.



      If the class of objects is proper, is it possible for the collection of arrows to still be a set?



      A not-convincing argument against it is that each object gets an identity arrow therefore there are "too many" arrows to be a set. I don't trust intuitions about size with things as big as $textSet$ though.



      A not-convincing argument that it's plausible is that arrows are opaque and I, the category-maker, get to freely pick the labels for the arrows, the definition of the composition relation, and the source and destination for each of the arrow-labels. How do I show that I can't come up with a set of labels big enough to label all of my arrows?




      ✱ I don't know whether it makes sense to start with a "possibly-proper class of all sets satisfying some predicate" and then inspect the class in some way to see if it's a proper class or not.










      share|cite|improve this question















      In some categories, like $textSet$ or $textGroup$, the objects are "constructed" out of sets (or are sets, possibly with additional structure). In order to avoid paradoxes, the collection of objects is therefore a proper class✱.



      If the class of objects is proper, is it possible for the collection of arrows to still be a set?



      A not-convincing argument against it is that each object gets an identity arrow therefore there are "too many" arrows to be a set. I don't trust intuitions about size with things as big as $textSet$ though.



      A not-convincing argument that it's plausible is that arrows are opaque and I, the category-maker, get to freely pick the labels for the arrows, the definition of the composition relation, and the source and destination for each of the arrow-labels. How do I show that I can't come up with a set of labels big enough to label all of my arrows?




      ✱ I don't know whether it makes sense to start with a "possibly-proper class of all sets satisfying some predicate" and then inspect the class in some way to see if it's a proper class or not.







      elementary-set-theory category-theory






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited 57 mins ago

























      asked 1 hour ago









      Gregory Nisbet

      29019




      29019




















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          2
          down vote



          accepted










          It is possible to have a category whose objects are a proper class and yet the arrows form set, in fact they can form a singleton. Consider for example the category $mathcalC$ whose objects is the class of all sets. We let $hom(a,b) = emptyset$ unless $a = b$ in which case we let $hom(a,a) = * $ for some fixed set $*$. We furthermore define composition via $* circ * := *$. This is a category with a proper class of objects and only one arrow.




          Let me add the following: If you are only interested in categories from the point of view as a category theorist (and not as a set theorist), you can, without loss of generality, assume that for any given category $mathcalC$ we have $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ and here's why:



          Given $mathcalC$ construct a new category $mathcalD$ with the same objects as $mathcalC$ and such that, for $a,b in mathrmob(mathcalD)$
          $$
          hom_mathcalD(a,b) := (a,b,f) mid f in hom_mathcalC(a,b)
          $$

          and
          $$
          (b,c,f) circ_mathcalD (a,b,g) := (a,c, f circ_mathcalC g).
          $$

          $mathcalC$ and $mathcalD$ are equivalent from the point of view of category theory and moreover they preserve all sorts of nice set theoretical properties (e.g. $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalC_a$ is definable if and only if $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalD_a$ is definable).



          And $mathcalD$ satisfies that $a neq b implies mathrmid^mathcalD_a neq mathrmid^mathcalD_a$.






          share|cite|improve this answer






















          • ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            52 mins ago










          • @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
            – Stefan Mesken
            50 mins ago











          • I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
            – Gregory Nisbet
            42 mins ago






          • 1




            @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
            – Stefan Mesken
            39 mins ago










          • It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
            – Kevin Carlson
            17 mins ago

















          up vote
          3
          down vote













          They have to form a proper class as well.



          For every object there is an identity arrow, so there must be more (or, in a discrete category, equally many) arrows than objects.






          share|cite|improve this answer




















          • That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            55 mins ago






          • 1




            It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
            – Stefan Mesken
            53 mins ago










          • @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
            – Lukas Kofler
            44 mins ago






          • 1




            @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
            – Stefan Mesken
            43 mins ago











          • @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
            – John Douma
            36 mins ago











          Your Answer





          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          );
          );
          , "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function()
          var channelOptions =
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "69"
          ;
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
          createEditor();
          );

          else
          createEditor();

          );

          function createEditor()
          StackExchange.prepareEditor(
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: true,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          imageUploader:
          brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
          contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
          allowUrls: true
          ,
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          );



          );













           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2986127%2fif-the-objects-of-a-category-form-a-proper-class-do-the-arrows-necessarily-form%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest






























          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes








          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          2
          down vote



          accepted










          It is possible to have a category whose objects are a proper class and yet the arrows form set, in fact they can form a singleton. Consider for example the category $mathcalC$ whose objects is the class of all sets. We let $hom(a,b) = emptyset$ unless $a = b$ in which case we let $hom(a,a) = * $ for some fixed set $*$. We furthermore define composition via $* circ * := *$. This is a category with a proper class of objects and only one arrow.




          Let me add the following: If you are only interested in categories from the point of view as a category theorist (and not as a set theorist), you can, without loss of generality, assume that for any given category $mathcalC$ we have $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ and here's why:



          Given $mathcalC$ construct a new category $mathcalD$ with the same objects as $mathcalC$ and such that, for $a,b in mathrmob(mathcalD)$
          $$
          hom_mathcalD(a,b) := (a,b,f) mid f in hom_mathcalC(a,b)
          $$

          and
          $$
          (b,c,f) circ_mathcalD (a,b,g) := (a,c, f circ_mathcalC g).
          $$

          $mathcalC$ and $mathcalD$ are equivalent from the point of view of category theory and moreover they preserve all sorts of nice set theoretical properties (e.g. $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalC_a$ is definable if and only if $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalD_a$ is definable).



          And $mathcalD$ satisfies that $a neq b implies mathrmid^mathcalD_a neq mathrmid^mathcalD_a$.






          share|cite|improve this answer






















          • ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            52 mins ago










          • @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
            – Stefan Mesken
            50 mins ago











          • I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
            – Gregory Nisbet
            42 mins ago






          • 1




            @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
            – Stefan Mesken
            39 mins ago










          • It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
            – Kevin Carlson
            17 mins ago














          up vote
          2
          down vote



          accepted










          It is possible to have a category whose objects are a proper class and yet the arrows form set, in fact they can form a singleton. Consider for example the category $mathcalC$ whose objects is the class of all sets. We let $hom(a,b) = emptyset$ unless $a = b$ in which case we let $hom(a,a) = * $ for some fixed set $*$. We furthermore define composition via $* circ * := *$. This is a category with a proper class of objects and only one arrow.




          Let me add the following: If you are only interested in categories from the point of view as a category theorist (and not as a set theorist), you can, without loss of generality, assume that for any given category $mathcalC$ we have $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ and here's why:



          Given $mathcalC$ construct a new category $mathcalD$ with the same objects as $mathcalC$ and such that, for $a,b in mathrmob(mathcalD)$
          $$
          hom_mathcalD(a,b) := (a,b,f) mid f in hom_mathcalC(a,b)
          $$

          and
          $$
          (b,c,f) circ_mathcalD (a,b,g) := (a,c, f circ_mathcalC g).
          $$

          $mathcalC$ and $mathcalD$ are equivalent from the point of view of category theory and moreover they preserve all sorts of nice set theoretical properties (e.g. $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalC_a$ is definable if and only if $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalD_a$ is definable).



          And $mathcalD$ satisfies that $a neq b implies mathrmid^mathcalD_a neq mathrmid^mathcalD_a$.






          share|cite|improve this answer






















          • ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            52 mins ago










          • @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
            – Stefan Mesken
            50 mins ago











          • I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
            – Gregory Nisbet
            42 mins ago






          • 1




            @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
            – Stefan Mesken
            39 mins ago










          • It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
            – Kevin Carlson
            17 mins ago












          up vote
          2
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          2
          down vote



          accepted






          It is possible to have a category whose objects are a proper class and yet the arrows form set, in fact they can form a singleton. Consider for example the category $mathcalC$ whose objects is the class of all sets. We let $hom(a,b) = emptyset$ unless $a = b$ in which case we let $hom(a,a) = * $ for some fixed set $*$. We furthermore define composition via $* circ * := *$. This is a category with a proper class of objects and only one arrow.




          Let me add the following: If you are only interested in categories from the point of view as a category theorist (and not as a set theorist), you can, without loss of generality, assume that for any given category $mathcalC$ we have $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ and here's why:



          Given $mathcalC$ construct a new category $mathcalD$ with the same objects as $mathcalC$ and such that, for $a,b in mathrmob(mathcalD)$
          $$
          hom_mathcalD(a,b) := (a,b,f) mid f in hom_mathcalC(a,b)
          $$

          and
          $$
          (b,c,f) circ_mathcalD (a,b,g) := (a,c, f circ_mathcalC g).
          $$

          $mathcalC$ and $mathcalD$ are equivalent from the point of view of category theory and moreover they preserve all sorts of nice set theoretical properties (e.g. $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalC_a$ is definable if and only if $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalD_a$ is definable).



          And $mathcalD$ satisfies that $a neq b implies mathrmid^mathcalD_a neq mathrmid^mathcalD_a$.






          share|cite|improve this answer














          It is possible to have a category whose objects are a proper class and yet the arrows form set, in fact they can form a singleton. Consider for example the category $mathcalC$ whose objects is the class of all sets. We let $hom(a,b) = emptyset$ unless $a = b$ in which case we let $hom(a,a) = * $ for some fixed set $*$. We furthermore define composition via $* circ * := *$. This is a category with a proper class of objects and only one arrow.




          Let me add the following: If you are only interested in categories from the point of view as a category theorist (and not as a set theorist), you can, without loss of generality, assume that for any given category $mathcalC$ we have $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ and here's why:



          Given $mathcalC$ construct a new category $mathcalD$ with the same objects as $mathcalC$ and such that, for $a,b in mathrmob(mathcalD)$
          $$
          hom_mathcalD(a,b) := (a,b,f) mid f in hom_mathcalC(a,b)
          $$

          and
          $$
          (b,c,f) circ_mathcalD (a,b,g) := (a,c, f circ_mathcalC g).
          $$

          $mathcalC$ and $mathcalD$ are equivalent from the point of view of category theory and moreover they preserve all sorts of nice set theoretical properties (e.g. $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalC_a$ is definable if and only if $a mapsto mathrmid^mathcalD_a$ is definable).



          And $mathcalD$ satisfies that $a neq b implies mathrmid^mathcalD_a neq mathrmid^mathcalD_a$.







          share|cite|improve this answer














          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer








          edited 23 mins ago

























          answered 55 mins ago









          Stefan Mesken

          14k32045




          14k32045











          • ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            52 mins ago










          • @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
            – Stefan Mesken
            50 mins ago











          • I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
            – Gregory Nisbet
            42 mins ago






          • 1




            @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
            – Stefan Mesken
            39 mins ago










          • It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
            – Kevin Carlson
            17 mins ago
















          • ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            52 mins ago










          • @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
            – Stefan Mesken
            50 mins ago











          • I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
            – Gregory Nisbet
            42 mins ago






          • 1




            @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
            – Stefan Mesken
            39 mins ago










          • It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
            – Kevin Carlson
            17 mins ago















          ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
          – Gregory Nisbet
          52 mins ago




          ... so in order to "label" my arrows and define a category, I only need to come up with local/per-object-pair labels?
          – Gregory Nisbet
          52 mins ago












          @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
          – Stefan Mesken
          50 mins ago





          @GregoryNisbet I'm not sure what you are asking. In this example with have $mathrmid_a = *$ for all objects $a$, so we cannot read of $a$ from $mathrmid_a$.
          – Stefan Mesken
          50 mins ago













          I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
          – Gregory Nisbet
          42 mins ago




          I'm asking why $mathrmid_a = *$ is allowed at all ... or why it defines a category. I was under the impression that arrows with different source and destination objects cannot be equal ... and that that's a law that you need to satisfy to be a category. Relaxing that restriction so that only arrows in the same homset need to be distinct is cool, but I don't know why it's okay to do.
          – Gregory Nisbet
          42 mins ago




          1




          1




          @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
          – Stefan Mesken
          39 mins ago




          @GregoryNisbet My definition of category is the one found on Wikipedia and it allows for the possiblity that arrows with different domains and codomains are still the same object. Granted, this isn't the case in any natural example that I can think of, but the question was whether the arrows necessarily form a proper class. The above shows that, while this usually is the case, this isn't necessarily true.
          – Stefan Mesken
          39 mins ago












          It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
          – Kevin Carlson
          17 mins ago




          It is a convention for some authors that no distinct arrows can be equal.
          – Kevin Carlson
          17 mins ago










          up vote
          3
          down vote













          They have to form a proper class as well.



          For every object there is an identity arrow, so there must be more (or, in a discrete category, equally many) arrows than objects.






          share|cite|improve this answer




















          • That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            55 mins ago






          • 1




            It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
            – Stefan Mesken
            53 mins ago










          • @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
            – Lukas Kofler
            44 mins ago






          • 1




            @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
            – Stefan Mesken
            43 mins ago











          • @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
            – John Douma
            36 mins ago















          up vote
          3
          down vote













          They have to form a proper class as well.



          For every object there is an identity arrow, so there must be more (or, in a discrete category, equally many) arrows than objects.






          share|cite|improve this answer




















          • That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            55 mins ago






          • 1




            It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
            – Stefan Mesken
            53 mins ago










          • @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
            – Lukas Kofler
            44 mins ago






          • 1




            @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
            – Stefan Mesken
            43 mins ago











          • @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
            – John Douma
            36 mins ago













          up vote
          3
          down vote










          up vote
          3
          down vote









          They have to form a proper class as well.



          For every object there is an identity arrow, so there must be more (or, in a discrete category, equally many) arrows than objects.






          share|cite|improve this answer












          They have to form a proper class as well.



          For every object there is an identity arrow, so there must be more (or, in a discrete category, equally many) arrows than objects.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered 1 hour ago









          Lukas Kofler

          1,0171519




          1,0171519











          • That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            55 mins ago






          • 1




            It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
            – Stefan Mesken
            53 mins ago










          • @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
            – Lukas Kofler
            44 mins ago






          • 1




            @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
            – Stefan Mesken
            43 mins ago











          • @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
            – John Douma
            36 mins ago

















          • That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
            – Gregory Nisbet
            55 mins ago






          • 1




            It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
            – Stefan Mesken
            53 mins ago










          • @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
            – Lukas Kofler
            44 mins ago






          • 1




            @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
            – Stefan Mesken
            43 mins ago











          • @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
            – John Douma
            36 mins ago
















          That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
          – Gregory Nisbet
          55 mins ago




          That makes sense. How do I show that an injection coming from a proper class always goes to a proper class and can't go to a set?
          – Gregory Nisbet
          55 mins ago




          1




          1




          It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
          – Stefan Mesken
          53 mins ago




          It may be that we have a different definition of "category". But I disagree with this answer, since it needn't be that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ (though this is true in many/most/all natural examples).
          – Stefan Mesken
          53 mins ago












          @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
          – Lukas Kofler
          44 mins ago




          @StefanMesken there are different views on this, agreed. I have seen the requirement you‘re referencing being added to the definition of a category, though I am not sure where.
          – Lukas Kofler
          44 mins ago




          1




          1




          @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
          – Stefan Mesken
          43 mins ago





          @LukasKofler I looked up his definition (here) and my example fits. So you may want to add the assumption that $a neq b implies mathrmid_a neq mathrmid_b$ to be valid. (Beyond that, depending on your background theory, there still might be a slight issue. Namely that $a mapsto mathrmid_a$ also should be definable. Otherwise there are really pathological counterexamples that most mathematicians would probably be very annoyed with...)
          – Stefan Mesken
          43 mins ago













          @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
          – John Douma
          36 mins ago





          @StefanMesken We can eliminate objects all together and identify $A$ with $id_A$. Do you have an example category where $ane b$ but $id_a=id_b$?
          – John Douma
          36 mins ago


















           

          draft saved


          draft discarded















































           


          draft saved


          draft discarded














          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2986127%2fif-the-objects-of-a-category-form-a-proper-class-do-the-arrows-necessarily-form%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest













































































          Comments

          Popular posts from this blog

          What does second last employer means? [closed]

          Installing NextGIS Connect into QGIS 3?

          One-line joke