Cardinality less than the natural numbers is finite

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
3
down vote

favorite












If we have a set S such that #(S)<#(N), where N is the set of the natural numbers, how would one prove that S must be finite? Is the axiom of choice relevant for such a proof? If so, what is a proof that doesn't require the axiom of choice?










share|cite|improve this question

























    up vote
    3
    down vote

    favorite












    If we have a set S such that #(S)<#(N), where N is the set of the natural numbers, how would one prove that S must be finite? Is the axiom of choice relevant for such a proof? If so, what is a proof that doesn't require the axiom of choice?










    share|cite|improve this question























      up vote
      3
      down vote

      favorite









      up vote
      3
      down vote

      favorite











      If we have a set S such that #(S)<#(N), where N is the set of the natural numbers, how would one prove that S must be finite? Is the axiom of choice relevant for such a proof? If so, what is a proof that doesn't require the axiom of choice?










      share|cite|improve this question













      If we have a set S such that #(S)<#(N), where N is the set of the natural numbers, how would one prove that S must be finite? Is the axiom of choice relevant for such a proof? If so, what is a proof that doesn't require the axiom of choice?







      elementary-set-theory set-theory axiom-of-choice






      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question











      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question










      asked 59 mins ago









      A. Smith

      503




      503




















          3 Answers
          3






          active

          oldest

          votes

















          up vote
          3
          down vote













          By definition of $<$ for cardinalities, there exists an injection $fcolon Sto Bbb N$. For $ninBbb N$ let $h(n)=|,xin f(S)mid x<n,|$. If $h$ is bounded, $h(n)<M$ for all $n$, this shows that $f(s)<M$ for all $sin S$, hence $f$ can be viewed as map $to0,ldots, M$ and $S$ is finite; on the other hand, if $h$ is not bounded, for $ninBbb N$ let $m=min,kinBbb Nmid h(j)ge n,$, observe that then $min f(S)$, and define $g(n)=f^-1(m)$. This gives us an injection (in fact, bijection) $Bbb Nto S$.






          share|cite|improve this answer





























            up vote
            1
            down vote













            Assuming $$# (s)<#(Bbb N)$$ we do not need choice, we just need to take the smallest element after the previous one, if it is finite it will end, if it is not finite than it will create bijective from $S$ to $Bbb N$, and thus $# (S)=# (Bbb N)$, this is contradiction thus $# (s)<#(Bbb N)$ implies $S$ is finite.



            But assuming $$# (s)notge#(Bbb N)$$is not enough to show $S$ is finite without choice! There exists infinite finite-dedekind set which is not comparable to $Bbb N$! But if you assume the axiom us choice it is provable that those sets do not exists.






            share|cite|improve this answer





























              up vote
              0
              down vote













              I think you can prove this by assuming that a set is infinite, you can clearly select an element and by definition of infinity you can select another element ad infinitum and you can enumerate the element that you selected at step as n.






              share|cite|improve this answer
















              • 1




                That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                – Asaf Karagila♦
                27 mins ago










              Your Answer




              StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
              return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
              StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
              StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
              );
              );
              , "mathjax-editing");

              StackExchange.ready(function()
              var channelOptions =
              tags: "".split(" "),
              id: "69"
              ;
              initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

              StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
              // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
              if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
              StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
              createEditor();
              );

              else
              createEditor();

              );

              function createEditor()
              StackExchange.prepareEditor(
              heartbeatType: 'answer',
              convertImagesToLinks: true,
              noModals: false,
              showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
              reputationToPostImages: 10,
              bindNavPrevention: true,
              postfix: "",
              noCode: true, onDemand: true,
              discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
              ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
              );



              );













               

              draft saved


              draft discarded


















              StackExchange.ready(
              function ()
              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2922411%2fcardinality-less-than-the-natural-numbers-is-finite%23new-answer', 'question_page');

              );

              Post as a guest






























              3 Answers
              3






              active

              oldest

              votes








              3 Answers
              3






              active

              oldest

              votes









              active

              oldest

              votes






              active

              oldest

              votes








              up vote
              3
              down vote













              By definition of $<$ for cardinalities, there exists an injection $fcolon Sto Bbb N$. For $ninBbb N$ let $h(n)=|,xin f(S)mid x<n,|$. If $h$ is bounded, $h(n)<M$ for all $n$, this shows that $f(s)<M$ for all $sin S$, hence $f$ can be viewed as map $to0,ldots, M$ and $S$ is finite; on the other hand, if $h$ is not bounded, for $ninBbb N$ let $m=min,kinBbb Nmid h(j)ge n,$, observe that then $min f(S)$, and define $g(n)=f^-1(m)$. This gives us an injection (in fact, bijection) $Bbb Nto S$.






              share|cite|improve this answer


























                up vote
                3
                down vote













                By definition of $<$ for cardinalities, there exists an injection $fcolon Sto Bbb N$. For $ninBbb N$ let $h(n)=|,xin f(S)mid x<n,|$. If $h$ is bounded, $h(n)<M$ for all $n$, this shows that $f(s)<M$ for all $sin S$, hence $f$ can be viewed as map $to0,ldots, M$ and $S$ is finite; on the other hand, if $h$ is not bounded, for $ninBbb N$ let $m=min,kinBbb Nmid h(j)ge n,$, observe that then $min f(S)$, and define $g(n)=f^-1(m)$. This gives us an injection (in fact, bijection) $Bbb Nto S$.






                share|cite|improve this answer
























                  up vote
                  3
                  down vote










                  up vote
                  3
                  down vote









                  By definition of $<$ for cardinalities, there exists an injection $fcolon Sto Bbb N$. For $ninBbb N$ let $h(n)=|,xin f(S)mid x<n,|$. If $h$ is bounded, $h(n)<M$ for all $n$, this shows that $f(s)<M$ for all $sin S$, hence $f$ can be viewed as map $to0,ldots, M$ and $S$ is finite; on the other hand, if $h$ is not bounded, for $ninBbb N$ let $m=min,kinBbb Nmid h(j)ge n,$, observe that then $min f(S)$, and define $g(n)=f^-1(m)$. This gives us an injection (in fact, bijection) $Bbb Nto S$.






                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  By definition of $<$ for cardinalities, there exists an injection $fcolon Sto Bbb N$. For $ninBbb N$ let $h(n)=|,xin f(S)mid x<n,|$. If $h$ is bounded, $h(n)<M$ for all $n$, this shows that $f(s)<M$ for all $sin S$, hence $f$ can be viewed as map $to0,ldots, M$ and $S$ is finite; on the other hand, if $h$ is not bounded, for $ninBbb N$ let $m=min,kinBbb Nmid h(j)ge n,$, observe that then $min f(S)$, and define $g(n)=f^-1(m)$. This gives us an injection (in fact, bijection) $Bbb Nto S$.







                  share|cite|improve this answer














                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer








                  edited 15 mins ago









                  Alon Amit

                  10.5k3766




                  10.5k3766










                  answered 43 mins ago









                  Hagen von Eitzen

                  267k21259482




                  267k21259482




















                      up vote
                      1
                      down vote













                      Assuming $$# (s)<#(Bbb N)$$ we do not need choice, we just need to take the smallest element after the previous one, if it is finite it will end, if it is not finite than it will create bijective from $S$ to $Bbb N$, and thus $# (S)=# (Bbb N)$, this is contradiction thus $# (s)<#(Bbb N)$ implies $S$ is finite.



                      But assuming $$# (s)notge#(Bbb N)$$is not enough to show $S$ is finite without choice! There exists infinite finite-dedekind set which is not comparable to $Bbb N$! But if you assume the axiom us choice it is provable that those sets do not exists.






                      share|cite|improve this answer


























                        up vote
                        1
                        down vote













                        Assuming $$# (s)<#(Bbb N)$$ we do not need choice, we just need to take the smallest element after the previous one, if it is finite it will end, if it is not finite than it will create bijective from $S$ to $Bbb N$, and thus $# (S)=# (Bbb N)$, this is contradiction thus $# (s)<#(Bbb N)$ implies $S$ is finite.



                        But assuming $$# (s)notge#(Bbb N)$$is not enough to show $S$ is finite without choice! There exists infinite finite-dedekind set which is not comparable to $Bbb N$! But if you assume the axiom us choice it is provable that those sets do not exists.






                        share|cite|improve this answer
























                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote










                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote









                          Assuming $$# (s)<#(Bbb N)$$ we do not need choice, we just need to take the smallest element after the previous one, if it is finite it will end, if it is not finite than it will create bijective from $S$ to $Bbb N$, and thus $# (S)=# (Bbb N)$, this is contradiction thus $# (s)<#(Bbb N)$ implies $S$ is finite.



                          But assuming $$# (s)notge#(Bbb N)$$is not enough to show $S$ is finite without choice! There exists infinite finite-dedekind set which is not comparable to $Bbb N$! But if you assume the axiom us choice it is provable that those sets do not exists.






                          share|cite|improve this answer














                          Assuming $$# (s)<#(Bbb N)$$ we do not need choice, we just need to take the smallest element after the previous one, if it is finite it will end, if it is not finite than it will create bijective from $S$ to $Bbb N$, and thus $# (S)=# (Bbb N)$, this is contradiction thus $# (s)<#(Bbb N)$ implies $S$ is finite.



                          But assuming $$# (s)notge#(Bbb N)$$is not enough to show $S$ is finite without choice! There exists infinite finite-dedekind set which is not comparable to $Bbb N$! But if you assume the axiom us choice it is provable that those sets do not exists.







                          share|cite|improve this answer














                          share|cite|improve this answer



                          share|cite|improve this answer








                          edited 12 mins ago

























                          answered 18 mins ago









                          Holo

                          4,6922729




                          4,6922729




















                              up vote
                              0
                              down vote













                              I think you can prove this by assuming that a set is infinite, you can clearly select an element and by definition of infinity you can select another element ad infinitum and you can enumerate the element that you selected at step as n.






                              share|cite|improve this answer
















                              • 1




                                That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                                – Asaf Karagila♦
                                27 mins ago














                              up vote
                              0
                              down vote













                              I think you can prove this by assuming that a set is infinite, you can clearly select an element and by definition of infinity you can select another element ad infinitum and you can enumerate the element that you selected at step as n.






                              share|cite|improve this answer
















                              • 1




                                That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                                – Asaf Karagila♦
                                27 mins ago












                              up vote
                              0
                              down vote










                              up vote
                              0
                              down vote









                              I think you can prove this by assuming that a set is infinite, you can clearly select an element and by definition of infinity you can select another element ad infinitum and you can enumerate the element that you selected at step as n.






                              share|cite|improve this answer












                              I think you can prove this by assuming that a set is infinite, you can clearly select an element and by definition of infinity you can select another element ad infinitum and you can enumerate the element that you selected at step as n.







                              share|cite|improve this answer












                              share|cite|improve this answer



                              share|cite|improve this answer










                              answered 37 mins ago









                              alper akyuz

                              1608




                              1608







                              • 1




                                That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                                – Asaf Karagila♦
                                27 mins ago












                              • 1




                                That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                                – Asaf Karagila♦
                                27 mins ago







                              1




                              1




                              That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                              – Asaf Karagila♦
                              27 mins ago




                              That is exactly the proof that requires the axiom of choice.
                              – Asaf Karagila♦
                              27 mins ago

















                               

                              draft saved


                              draft discarded















































                               


                              draft saved


                              draft discarded














                              StackExchange.ready(
                              function ()
                              StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2922411%2fcardinality-less-than-the-natural-numbers-is-finite%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                              );

                              Post as a guest













































































                              Comments

                              Popular posts from this blog

                              What does second last employer means? [closed]

                              Installing NextGIS Connect into QGIS 3?

                              One-line joke