Relation between the Axiom of Choice and a the existence of a hyperplane not containing a vector

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
4
down vote

favorite












In a lot of problems in linear one uses the existence, for each $E$ vectorial space over a field $k$ , and each $xin E$, of a Hyperplane $H$ such that $E=kcdot x oplus H$ (Let us denote $mathcalP$ this property). With Zorn's Lemma, the existence of a such $H$ is trivial. However, as this seems weaker than the existence of a basis of $E$, maybe $mathcalP$ does not imply the Axiom of choice. Thus my question is : is $mathcalP$ equivalent to the Axiom of Choice and if not, is there a weaker form of the Axiom of Choice equivalent to $mathcalP$ ?










share|cite|improve this question

















  • 2




    Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
    – Wojowu
    4 hours ago














up vote
4
down vote

favorite












In a lot of problems in linear one uses the existence, for each $E$ vectorial space over a field $k$ , and each $xin E$, of a Hyperplane $H$ such that $E=kcdot x oplus H$ (Let us denote $mathcalP$ this property). With Zorn's Lemma, the existence of a such $H$ is trivial. However, as this seems weaker than the existence of a basis of $E$, maybe $mathcalP$ does not imply the Axiom of choice. Thus my question is : is $mathcalP$ equivalent to the Axiom of Choice and if not, is there a weaker form of the Axiom of Choice equivalent to $mathcalP$ ?










share|cite|improve this question

















  • 2




    Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
    – Wojowu
    4 hours ago












up vote
4
down vote

favorite









up vote
4
down vote

favorite











In a lot of problems in linear one uses the existence, for each $E$ vectorial space over a field $k$ , and each $xin E$, of a Hyperplane $H$ such that $E=kcdot x oplus H$ (Let us denote $mathcalP$ this property). With Zorn's Lemma, the existence of a such $H$ is trivial. However, as this seems weaker than the existence of a basis of $E$, maybe $mathcalP$ does not imply the Axiom of choice. Thus my question is : is $mathcalP$ equivalent to the Axiom of Choice and if not, is there a weaker form of the Axiom of Choice equivalent to $mathcalP$ ?










share|cite|improve this question













In a lot of problems in linear one uses the existence, for each $E$ vectorial space over a field $k$ , and each $xin E$, of a Hyperplane $H$ such that $E=kcdot x oplus H$ (Let us denote $mathcalP$ this property). With Zorn's Lemma, the existence of a such $H$ is trivial. However, as this seems weaker than the existence of a basis of $E$, maybe $mathcalP$ does not imply the Axiom of choice. Thus my question is : is $mathcalP$ equivalent to the Axiom of Choice and if not, is there a weaker form of the Axiom of Choice equivalent to $mathcalP$ ?







axiom-of-choice vector-spaces






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 4 hours ago









Swann

404




404







  • 2




    Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
    – Wojowu
    4 hours ago












  • 2




    Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
    – Wojowu
    4 hours ago







2




2




Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
– Wojowu
4 hours ago




Just for the record, choice is definitely necessary to show this result: taking $E$ to be $mathbb R$ as $mathbb Q$-vector space, $H$ would have to be a subset of $mathbb R$ isomorphic to $mathbb R/mathbb Q$, but it is consistent that this set can't be linearly ordered.
– Wojowu
4 hours ago










1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
4
down vote













It is not hard to see that this statement is equivalent to "In every vector space, for every vector $v$ there is a functional $f$ such that $f(v)=1$".



If $cal P$ holds, then the projection onto $kcdot x$ is a linear functional which is nontrivial; if there is a nontrivial functional then choose $x$ which is mapped to $1_k$, and consider $H$ as the kernel of the functional. Some $cal P$ is equivalent to "If $V$ is nontrivial, then $V^*$ is nontrivial".



As of October 2018, it is still unknown whether or not this is equivalent to the axiom of choice in full. But there are some intermediate results, for example it is consistent that there is a vector space over a field $k$ whose dual is trivial, for any fixed $k$. Moreover, this is consistent with $sf DC_kappa$ for any prescribed $kappa$.



One should remark that restricting to Banach spaces and continuous functionals, the nontriviality of the [topological] dual is equivalent to the Hahn–Banach theorem.



Let me also add that Marianne Morillon showed that in $sf ZFA$, $cal P(Bbb Q)$, namely restricting our attention to vector spaces over $Bbb Q$, is not enough to deduce that every vector space over $Bbb Q$ admits a basis, and that a weaker form of choice called "Axiom of Multiple Choice" implies $cal P$ for fields of characteristics $0$.




Morillon, Marianne, Linear forms and axioms of choice., Commentat. Math. Univ. Carol. 50, No. 3, 421-431 (2009). ZBL1212.03034.




These two facts are not telling us a whole lot about what happens in $sf ZF$, since in $sf ZF$ the axiom of multiple choice implies full choice and existence of bases over $Bbb Q$ implies full choice.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
    – áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
    3 hours ago










  • I have literally no idea what any of that means.
    – Asaf Karagila
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
    – Wojowu
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
    – Andreas Blass
    1 hour ago










Your Answer




StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "504"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: false,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f313464%2frelation-between-the-axiom-of-choice-and-a-the-existence-of-a-hyperplane-not-con%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
4
down vote













It is not hard to see that this statement is equivalent to "In every vector space, for every vector $v$ there is a functional $f$ such that $f(v)=1$".



If $cal P$ holds, then the projection onto $kcdot x$ is a linear functional which is nontrivial; if there is a nontrivial functional then choose $x$ which is mapped to $1_k$, and consider $H$ as the kernel of the functional. Some $cal P$ is equivalent to "If $V$ is nontrivial, then $V^*$ is nontrivial".



As of October 2018, it is still unknown whether or not this is equivalent to the axiom of choice in full. But there are some intermediate results, for example it is consistent that there is a vector space over a field $k$ whose dual is trivial, for any fixed $k$. Moreover, this is consistent with $sf DC_kappa$ for any prescribed $kappa$.



One should remark that restricting to Banach spaces and continuous functionals, the nontriviality of the [topological] dual is equivalent to the Hahn–Banach theorem.



Let me also add that Marianne Morillon showed that in $sf ZFA$, $cal P(Bbb Q)$, namely restricting our attention to vector spaces over $Bbb Q$, is not enough to deduce that every vector space over $Bbb Q$ admits a basis, and that a weaker form of choice called "Axiom of Multiple Choice" implies $cal P$ for fields of characteristics $0$.




Morillon, Marianne, Linear forms and axioms of choice., Commentat. Math. Univ. Carol. 50, No. 3, 421-431 (2009). ZBL1212.03034.




These two facts are not telling us a whole lot about what happens in $sf ZF$, since in $sf ZF$ the axiom of multiple choice implies full choice and existence of bases over $Bbb Q$ implies full choice.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
    – áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
    3 hours ago










  • I have literally no idea what any of that means.
    – Asaf Karagila
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
    – Wojowu
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
    – Andreas Blass
    1 hour ago














up vote
4
down vote













It is not hard to see that this statement is equivalent to "In every vector space, for every vector $v$ there is a functional $f$ such that $f(v)=1$".



If $cal P$ holds, then the projection onto $kcdot x$ is a linear functional which is nontrivial; if there is a nontrivial functional then choose $x$ which is mapped to $1_k$, and consider $H$ as the kernel of the functional. Some $cal P$ is equivalent to "If $V$ is nontrivial, then $V^*$ is nontrivial".



As of October 2018, it is still unknown whether or not this is equivalent to the axiom of choice in full. But there are some intermediate results, for example it is consistent that there is a vector space over a field $k$ whose dual is trivial, for any fixed $k$. Moreover, this is consistent with $sf DC_kappa$ for any prescribed $kappa$.



One should remark that restricting to Banach spaces and continuous functionals, the nontriviality of the [topological] dual is equivalent to the Hahn–Banach theorem.



Let me also add that Marianne Morillon showed that in $sf ZFA$, $cal P(Bbb Q)$, namely restricting our attention to vector spaces over $Bbb Q$, is not enough to deduce that every vector space over $Bbb Q$ admits a basis, and that a weaker form of choice called "Axiom of Multiple Choice" implies $cal P$ for fields of characteristics $0$.




Morillon, Marianne, Linear forms and axioms of choice., Commentat. Math. Univ. Carol. 50, No. 3, 421-431 (2009). ZBL1212.03034.




These two facts are not telling us a whole lot about what happens in $sf ZF$, since in $sf ZF$ the axiom of multiple choice implies full choice and existence of bases over $Bbb Q$ implies full choice.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
    – áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
    3 hours ago










  • I have literally no idea what any of that means.
    – Asaf Karagila
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
    – Wojowu
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
    – Andreas Blass
    1 hour ago












up vote
4
down vote










up vote
4
down vote









It is not hard to see that this statement is equivalent to "In every vector space, for every vector $v$ there is a functional $f$ such that $f(v)=1$".



If $cal P$ holds, then the projection onto $kcdot x$ is a linear functional which is nontrivial; if there is a nontrivial functional then choose $x$ which is mapped to $1_k$, and consider $H$ as the kernel of the functional. Some $cal P$ is equivalent to "If $V$ is nontrivial, then $V^*$ is nontrivial".



As of October 2018, it is still unknown whether or not this is equivalent to the axiom of choice in full. But there are some intermediate results, for example it is consistent that there is a vector space over a field $k$ whose dual is trivial, for any fixed $k$. Moreover, this is consistent with $sf DC_kappa$ for any prescribed $kappa$.



One should remark that restricting to Banach spaces and continuous functionals, the nontriviality of the [topological] dual is equivalent to the Hahn–Banach theorem.



Let me also add that Marianne Morillon showed that in $sf ZFA$, $cal P(Bbb Q)$, namely restricting our attention to vector spaces over $Bbb Q$, is not enough to deduce that every vector space over $Bbb Q$ admits a basis, and that a weaker form of choice called "Axiom of Multiple Choice" implies $cal P$ for fields of characteristics $0$.




Morillon, Marianne, Linear forms and axioms of choice., Commentat. Math. Univ. Carol. 50, No. 3, 421-431 (2009). ZBL1212.03034.




These two facts are not telling us a whole lot about what happens in $sf ZF$, since in $sf ZF$ the axiom of multiple choice implies full choice and existence of bases over $Bbb Q$ implies full choice.






share|cite|improve this answer














It is not hard to see that this statement is equivalent to "In every vector space, for every vector $v$ there is a functional $f$ such that $f(v)=1$".



If $cal P$ holds, then the projection onto $kcdot x$ is a linear functional which is nontrivial; if there is a nontrivial functional then choose $x$ which is mapped to $1_k$, and consider $H$ as the kernel of the functional. Some $cal P$ is equivalent to "If $V$ is nontrivial, then $V^*$ is nontrivial".



As of October 2018, it is still unknown whether or not this is equivalent to the axiom of choice in full. But there are some intermediate results, for example it is consistent that there is a vector space over a field $k$ whose dual is trivial, for any fixed $k$. Moreover, this is consistent with $sf DC_kappa$ for any prescribed $kappa$.



One should remark that restricting to Banach spaces and continuous functionals, the nontriviality of the [topological] dual is equivalent to the Hahn–Banach theorem.



Let me also add that Marianne Morillon showed that in $sf ZFA$, $cal P(Bbb Q)$, namely restricting our attention to vector spaces over $Bbb Q$, is not enough to deduce that every vector space over $Bbb Q$ admits a basis, and that a weaker form of choice called "Axiom of Multiple Choice" implies $cal P$ for fields of characteristics $0$.




Morillon, Marianne, Linear forms and axioms of choice., Commentat. Math. Univ. Carol. 50, No. 3, 421-431 (2009). ZBL1212.03034.




These two facts are not telling us a whole lot about what happens in $sf ZF$, since in $sf ZF$ the axiom of multiple choice implies full choice and existence of bases over $Bbb Q$ implies full choice.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 22 mins ago

























answered 3 hours ago









Asaf Karagila

20.4k673171




20.4k673171











  • Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
    – áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
    3 hours ago










  • I have literally no idea what any of that means.
    – Asaf Karagila
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
    – Wojowu
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
    – Andreas Blass
    1 hour ago
















  • Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
    – áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
    3 hours ago










  • I have literally no idea what any of that means.
    – Asaf Karagila
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
    – Wojowu
    3 hours ago






  • 1




    @მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
    – Asaf Karagila
    2 hours ago






  • 1




    The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
    – Andreas Blass
    1 hour ago















Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
– áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
3 hours ago




Would not the dual of a line bundle without nonzero sections provide an example of a nonzero (in fact, 1-dimensional) vector space without nonzero functionals on it? More precisely, the space of such functionals would be 1-dimensional itself but would fail to have any (global) elements.
– áƒ›áƒáƒ›áƒ£áƒ™áƒ ჯიბლაძე
3 hours ago












I have literally no idea what any of that means.
– Asaf Karagila
3 hours ago




I have literally no idea what any of that means.
– Asaf Karagila
3 hours ago




1




1




@მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
– Wojowu
3 hours ago




@მამუკაჯიბლაძე 1-dimensional vector space always has nonzero functionals - if $v$ is nonzero vector, then every vector is of the form $alpha v$ and $alpha vmapstoalpha$ is a nonzero functional. I think your confusion might arise from misunderstanding what "nonzero" here is supposed to mean - it just means any functional which is not zero everywhere. This is different from vector bundle terminology, where "nonzero" means that it's everywhere nonzero.
– Wojowu
3 hours ago




1




1




@მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
– Asaf Karagila
2 hours ago




@მამუკაჯიბლაძე: Again, I am not sure what you mean. But feel free to send me an email with details. My address can be found through my profile.
– Asaf Karagila
2 hours ago




1




1




The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
– Andreas Blass
1 hour ago




The statement in the question was "for each $x$ ... there is $H$ ...." So I think the equivalent statement should not be just that there is a non-zero linear functional but that, for each vector $xneq 0$, there is a linear functional $f$ with $f(x)neq0$.
– Andreas Blass
1 hour ago

















 

draft saved


draft discarded















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f313464%2frelation-between-the-axiom-of-choice-and-a-the-existence-of-a-hyperplane-not-con%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

What does second last employer means? [closed]

Installing NextGIS Connect into QGIS 3?

One-line joke