Difference between first and second order induction?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
2
down vote

favorite












Can anyone explain the difference between induction as it's stated in first order logic and that from second order logic? I don't understand the difference as it pertains to things like Peano axioms.










share|cite|improve this question

















  • 3




    Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
    – realdonaldtrump
    3 hours ago











  • @realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
    – Carl Mummert
    14 secs ago















up vote
2
down vote

favorite












Can anyone explain the difference between induction as it's stated in first order logic and that from second order logic? I don't understand the difference as it pertains to things like Peano axioms.










share|cite|improve this question

















  • 3




    Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
    – realdonaldtrump
    3 hours ago











  • @realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
    – Carl Mummert
    14 secs ago













up vote
2
down vote

favorite









up vote
2
down vote

favorite











Can anyone explain the difference between induction as it's stated in first order logic and that from second order logic? I don't understand the difference as it pertains to things like Peano axioms.










share|cite|improve this question













Can anyone explain the difference between induction as it's stated in first order logic and that from second order logic? I don't understand the difference as it pertains to things like Peano axioms.







logic induction definition peano-axioms






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 3 hours ago









user525966

1,943821




1,943821







  • 3




    Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
    – realdonaldtrump
    3 hours ago











  • @realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
    – Carl Mummert
    14 secs ago













  • 3




    Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
    – realdonaldtrump
    3 hours ago











  • @realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
    – Carl Mummert
    14 secs ago








3




3




Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
– realdonaldtrump
3 hours ago





Second-order induction is an axiom which applies to any set $Xsubseteq mathbbN$: if $0in X$ and $forall n(n in X rightarrow n+1in X)$, then $X=mathbbN$. First-order induction is an axiom (or, to be rigorous, a scheme of axioms) which works the same way but only applies to those set defined by some first-order formula $phi$, i.e., sets of the form $X= nin mathbbN: phi(n) mathrmis true$.
– realdonaldtrump
3 hours ago













@realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
– Carl Mummert
14 secs ago





@realdonaldtrump: of course, when we work in second-order arithmetic, the "first order induction scheme" includes the formula "$n in X$", and so the second-order induction axiom is just one particular axiom in the induction scheme.
– Carl Mummert
14 secs ago











1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
4
down vote













The informal statement of induction is:




For any property $P$ of natural numbers, if $P(0)$ holds, and $P(n)$ implies $P(n+1)$ for all $n$, then $P(n)$ holds for all $n$.




Of course, this raises the question: What exactly do we mean by a "property of natural numbers"?



One natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with sets of natural numbers. That is, for any property $P$, we can form the set of all natural numbers satisfying that property. And for any set of natural numbers $X$, we can consider the property of being in $X$. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the set $nin mathbbNmid ntext is prime$



Another natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with formulas in one free variable in some logic (in this discussion, let's just talk about first-order logic in the language of arithemetic). Here the syntax of the logic gives us a language for writing down properties of natural numbers. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the formula $lnot (x= 1)land forall y, (exists z, (ycdot z = x) rightarrow (y = 1 lor y = x))$.



Induction under the interpretation "properties are sets" can be formalized as follows:




$forall Psubseteq mathbbN: ((0in Pland forall nin mathbbN: (nin P rightarrow (n+1)in P))rightarrow forall nin mathbbN: nin P)$




This is a sentence of second-order logic, since it involves a quantification $forall Psubseteq mathbbN$ over subsets of $mathbbN$.



The interpretation "properties are formulas" leads to the following formalization of induction:




$(varphi(0)land forall n, (varphi(n)rightarrow varphi(n+1)) rightarrow forall n,varphi(n)$




Here we have an infinite schema of sentences of first-order logic, one for each first-order formula $varphi(x)$. It's first-order because the quantifiers only range over elements of $mathbbN$, not subsets, and the formulas $varphi(x)$ are themselves first-order.



It's worth noting that second-order induction is much stronger than first-order induction. Second-order induction applies to all subsets, while first-order induction only applies to those which can be defined by some first-order formula (and since there are are $2^aleph_0$-many subsets of $mathbbN$ and only $aleph_0$-many first-order formulas, there are many subsets which are not definable).



The second-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the second-order induction axiom above) suffice to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism.



The first-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the first-order induction axiom schema above) cannot hope to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism (thanks to the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). That is, there are "non-standard models" of the first-order Peano axioms, which satisfy induction for all first-order definable properties, but not for arbitrary subsets.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
    – Carl Mummert
    13 mins ago











  • Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
    – Carl Mummert
    9 mins ago











Your Answer





StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
);
);
, "mathjax-editing");

StackExchange.ready(function()
var channelOptions =
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
;
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
createEditor();
);

else
createEditor();

);

function createEditor()
StackExchange.prepareEditor(
heartbeatType: 'answer',
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader:
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
,
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
);



);













 

draft saved


draft discarded


















StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2984410%2fdifference-between-first-and-second-order-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest






























1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes








1 Answer
1






active

oldest

votes









active

oldest

votes






active

oldest

votes








up vote
4
down vote













The informal statement of induction is:




For any property $P$ of natural numbers, if $P(0)$ holds, and $P(n)$ implies $P(n+1)$ for all $n$, then $P(n)$ holds for all $n$.




Of course, this raises the question: What exactly do we mean by a "property of natural numbers"?



One natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with sets of natural numbers. That is, for any property $P$, we can form the set of all natural numbers satisfying that property. And for any set of natural numbers $X$, we can consider the property of being in $X$. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the set $nin mathbbNmid ntext is prime$



Another natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with formulas in one free variable in some logic (in this discussion, let's just talk about first-order logic in the language of arithemetic). Here the syntax of the logic gives us a language for writing down properties of natural numbers. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the formula $lnot (x= 1)land forall y, (exists z, (ycdot z = x) rightarrow (y = 1 lor y = x))$.



Induction under the interpretation "properties are sets" can be formalized as follows:




$forall Psubseteq mathbbN: ((0in Pland forall nin mathbbN: (nin P rightarrow (n+1)in P))rightarrow forall nin mathbbN: nin P)$




This is a sentence of second-order logic, since it involves a quantification $forall Psubseteq mathbbN$ over subsets of $mathbbN$.



The interpretation "properties are formulas" leads to the following formalization of induction:




$(varphi(0)land forall n, (varphi(n)rightarrow varphi(n+1)) rightarrow forall n,varphi(n)$




Here we have an infinite schema of sentences of first-order logic, one for each first-order formula $varphi(x)$. It's first-order because the quantifiers only range over elements of $mathbbN$, not subsets, and the formulas $varphi(x)$ are themselves first-order.



It's worth noting that second-order induction is much stronger than first-order induction. Second-order induction applies to all subsets, while first-order induction only applies to those which can be defined by some first-order formula (and since there are are $2^aleph_0$-many subsets of $mathbbN$ and only $aleph_0$-many first-order formulas, there are many subsets which are not definable).



The second-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the second-order induction axiom above) suffice to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism.



The first-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the first-order induction axiom schema above) cannot hope to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism (thanks to the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). That is, there are "non-standard models" of the first-order Peano axioms, which satisfy induction for all first-order definable properties, but not for arbitrary subsets.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
    – Carl Mummert
    13 mins ago











  • Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
    – Carl Mummert
    9 mins ago















up vote
4
down vote













The informal statement of induction is:




For any property $P$ of natural numbers, if $P(0)$ holds, and $P(n)$ implies $P(n+1)$ for all $n$, then $P(n)$ holds for all $n$.




Of course, this raises the question: What exactly do we mean by a "property of natural numbers"?



One natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with sets of natural numbers. That is, for any property $P$, we can form the set of all natural numbers satisfying that property. And for any set of natural numbers $X$, we can consider the property of being in $X$. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the set $nin mathbbNmid ntext is prime$



Another natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with formulas in one free variable in some logic (in this discussion, let's just talk about first-order logic in the language of arithemetic). Here the syntax of the logic gives us a language for writing down properties of natural numbers. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the formula $lnot (x= 1)land forall y, (exists z, (ycdot z = x) rightarrow (y = 1 lor y = x))$.



Induction under the interpretation "properties are sets" can be formalized as follows:




$forall Psubseteq mathbbN: ((0in Pland forall nin mathbbN: (nin P rightarrow (n+1)in P))rightarrow forall nin mathbbN: nin P)$




This is a sentence of second-order logic, since it involves a quantification $forall Psubseteq mathbbN$ over subsets of $mathbbN$.



The interpretation "properties are formulas" leads to the following formalization of induction:




$(varphi(0)land forall n, (varphi(n)rightarrow varphi(n+1)) rightarrow forall n,varphi(n)$




Here we have an infinite schema of sentences of first-order logic, one for each first-order formula $varphi(x)$. It's first-order because the quantifiers only range over elements of $mathbbN$, not subsets, and the formulas $varphi(x)$ are themselves first-order.



It's worth noting that second-order induction is much stronger than first-order induction. Second-order induction applies to all subsets, while first-order induction only applies to those which can be defined by some first-order formula (and since there are are $2^aleph_0$-many subsets of $mathbbN$ and only $aleph_0$-many first-order formulas, there are many subsets which are not definable).



The second-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the second-order induction axiom above) suffice to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism.



The first-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the first-order induction axiom schema above) cannot hope to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism (thanks to the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). That is, there are "non-standard models" of the first-order Peano axioms, which satisfy induction for all first-order definable properties, but not for arbitrary subsets.






share|cite|improve this answer






















  • It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
    – Carl Mummert
    13 mins ago











  • Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
    – Carl Mummert
    9 mins ago













up vote
4
down vote










up vote
4
down vote









The informal statement of induction is:




For any property $P$ of natural numbers, if $P(0)$ holds, and $P(n)$ implies $P(n+1)$ for all $n$, then $P(n)$ holds for all $n$.




Of course, this raises the question: What exactly do we mean by a "property of natural numbers"?



One natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with sets of natural numbers. That is, for any property $P$, we can form the set of all natural numbers satisfying that property. And for any set of natural numbers $X$, we can consider the property of being in $X$. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the set $nin mathbbNmid ntext is prime$



Another natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with formulas in one free variable in some logic (in this discussion, let's just talk about first-order logic in the language of arithemetic). Here the syntax of the logic gives us a language for writing down properties of natural numbers. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the formula $lnot (x= 1)land forall y, (exists z, (ycdot z = x) rightarrow (y = 1 lor y = x))$.



Induction under the interpretation "properties are sets" can be formalized as follows:




$forall Psubseteq mathbbN: ((0in Pland forall nin mathbbN: (nin P rightarrow (n+1)in P))rightarrow forall nin mathbbN: nin P)$




This is a sentence of second-order logic, since it involves a quantification $forall Psubseteq mathbbN$ over subsets of $mathbbN$.



The interpretation "properties are formulas" leads to the following formalization of induction:




$(varphi(0)land forall n, (varphi(n)rightarrow varphi(n+1)) rightarrow forall n,varphi(n)$




Here we have an infinite schema of sentences of first-order logic, one for each first-order formula $varphi(x)$. It's first-order because the quantifiers only range over elements of $mathbbN$, not subsets, and the formulas $varphi(x)$ are themselves first-order.



It's worth noting that second-order induction is much stronger than first-order induction. Second-order induction applies to all subsets, while first-order induction only applies to those which can be defined by some first-order formula (and since there are are $2^aleph_0$-many subsets of $mathbbN$ and only $aleph_0$-many first-order formulas, there are many subsets which are not definable).



The second-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the second-order induction axiom above) suffice to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism.



The first-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the first-order induction axiom schema above) cannot hope to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism (thanks to the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). That is, there are "non-standard models" of the first-order Peano axioms, which satisfy induction for all first-order definable properties, but not for arbitrary subsets.






share|cite|improve this answer














The informal statement of induction is:




For any property $P$ of natural numbers, if $P(0)$ holds, and $P(n)$ implies $P(n+1)$ for all $n$, then $P(n)$ holds for all $n$.




Of course, this raises the question: What exactly do we mean by a "property of natural numbers"?



One natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with sets of natural numbers. That is, for any property $P$, we can form the set of all natural numbers satisfying that property. And for any set of natural numbers $X$, we can consider the property of being in $X$. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the set $nin mathbbNmid ntext is prime$



Another natural interpretation is to identify properties of natural numbers with formulas in one free variable in some logic (in this discussion, let's just talk about first-order logic in the language of arithemetic). Here the syntax of the logic gives us a language for writing down properties of natural numbers. For example, the property of being a prime number corresponds to the formula $lnot (x= 1)land forall y, (exists z, (ycdot z = x) rightarrow (y = 1 lor y = x))$.



Induction under the interpretation "properties are sets" can be formalized as follows:




$forall Psubseteq mathbbN: ((0in Pland forall nin mathbbN: (nin P rightarrow (n+1)in P))rightarrow forall nin mathbbN: nin P)$




This is a sentence of second-order logic, since it involves a quantification $forall Psubseteq mathbbN$ over subsets of $mathbbN$.



The interpretation "properties are formulas" leads to the following formalization of induction:




$(varphi(0)land forall n, (varphi(n)rightarrow varphi(n+1)) rightarrow forall n,varphi(n)$




Here we have an infinite schema of sentences of first-order logic, one for each first-order formula $varphi(x)$. It's first-order because the quantifiers only range over elements of $mathbbN$, not subsets, and the formulas $varphi(x)$ are themselves first-order.



It's worth noting that second-order induction is much stronger than first-order induction. Second-order induction applies to all subsets, while first-order induction only applies to those which can be defined by some first-order formula (and since there are are $2^aleph_0$-many subsets of $mathbbN$ and only $aleph_0$-many first-order formulas, there are many subsets which are not definable).



The second-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the second-order induction axiom above) suffice to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism.



The first-order Peano axioms (which consist of some basic rules of arithmetic, together with the first-order induction axiom schema above) cannot hope to pin down $mathbbN$ up to isomorphism (thanks to the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems). That is, there are "non-standard models" of the first-order Peano axioms, which satisfy induction for all first-order definable properties, but not for arbitrary subsets.







share|cite|improve this answer














share|cite|improve this answer



share|cite|improve this answer








edited 2 hours ago

























answered 2 hours ago









Alex Kruckman

25.3k22455




25.3k22455











  • It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
    – Carl Mummert
    13 mins ago











  • Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
    – Carl Mummert
    9 mins ago

















  • It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
    – Carl Mummert
    13 mins ago











  • Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
    – Carl Mummert
    9 mins ago
















It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
– Carl Mummert
13 mins ago





It is true that second-order induction is stronger than first-order, but only when we are working in a context where we have strong comprehension axioms as well. For example, if we are working syntactically, and we want to prove some formula using second-order induction, we will have to construct the set $P$ in our formal proof before we can apply induction to it, and so the strength of the induction axiom will depend on which sets we can construct in our proofs - essentially reducing things to the question of which formulas have a comprehension axiom.
– Carl Mummert
13 mins ago













Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
– Carl Mummert
9 mins ago





Of course, when we work semantically with full second order semantics, in essence we have comprehension for all subsets of N, and so second-order induction is much stronger than the first-order induction scheme in that setting. But when we begin to look at particular formal theories, the relationship is more complex.
– Carl Mummert
9 mins ago


















 

draft saved


draft discarded















































 


draft saved


draft discarded














StackExchange.ready(
function ()
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2984410%2fdifference-between-first-and-second-order-induction%23new-answer', 'question_page');

);

Post as a guest













































































Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Long meetings (6-7 hours a day): Being “babysat” by supervisor

Is the Concept of Multiple Fantasy Races Scientifically Flawed? [closed]

Confectionery