“categorical” proof of a seemingly symmetric statement about Noetherian/Artinian modules

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
5
down vote

favorite












There are two statements which to me seem rather symmetric: Let $A$ be a ring, $M$ an $A$-module, and $f : M to M$.




If $M$ is Noetherian and $f$ is surjective, then $f$ is injective.



If $M$ is Artinian and $f$ is injective, then $f$ is surjective.




The proofs also seem symmetric in a sense: in the first case one constructs the increasing chain of ideals $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is surjective but not injective. In the second case one uses the injectivity of $f$ to construct the decreasing chain of ideals $M supset im , f supset im , f^2 supset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is injective but not surjective. However, some symmetry is lost in the assertion of the last part ("which is strict when $f$ is __ but not __"). In the first case I use the fact $ker f^n = ker f^n+1$ implies that $f$ is injective on $im , f^n = M$. In the second case I use the fact that $M supsetneq im , f$ would imply that $im , f^n supsetneq im , f^n+1$ because injective maps preserve strict inclusions.



My question is, is there a way to prove one of the statements in the appropriate category/framework such that the other follows from some kind of formulaic reversal of arrows? This is definitely more of a soft question because I'm not sure what this might mean, but the two situations seem symmetric enough that this might be plausible.










share|cite|improve this question





















  • Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
    – user10354138
    1 hour ago











  • @user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
    – MCT
    58 mins ago














up vote
5
down vote

favorite












There are two statements which to me seem rather symmetric: Let $A$ be a ring, $M$ an $A$-module, and $f : M to M$.




If $M$ is Noetherian and $f$ is surjective, then $f$ is injective.



If $M$ is Artinian and $f$ is injective, then $f$ is surjective.




The proofs also seem symmetric in a sense: in the first case one constructs the increasing chain of ideals $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is surjective but not injective. In the second case one uses the injectivity of $f$ to construct the decreasing chain of ideals $M supset im , f supset im , f^2 supset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is injective but not surjective. However, some symmetry is lost in the assertion of the last part ("which is strict when $f$ is __ but not __"). In the first case I use the fact $ker f^n = ker f^n+1$ implies that $f$ is injective on $im , f^n = M$. In the second case I use the fact that $M supsetneq im , f$ would imply that $im , f^n supsetneq im , f^n+1$ because injective maps preserve strict inclusions.



My question is, is there a way to prove one of the statements in the appropriate category/framework such that the other follows from some kind of formulaic reversal of arrows? This is definitely more of a soft question because I'm not sure what this might mean, but the two situations seem symmetric enough that this might be plausible.










share|cite|improve this question





















  • Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
    – user10354138
    1 hour ago











  • @user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
    – MCT
    58 mins ago












up vote
5
down vote

favorite









up vote
5
down vote

favorite











There are two statements which to me seem rather symmetric: Let $A$ be a ring, $M$ an $A$-module, and $f : M to M$.




If $M$ is Noetherian and $f$ is surjective, then $f$ is injective.



If $M$ is Artinian and $f$ is injective, then $f$ is surjective.




The proofs also seem symmetric in a sense: in the first case one constructs the increasing chain of ideals $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is surjective but not injective. In the second case one uses the injectivity of $f$ to construct the decreasing chain of ideals $M supset im , f supset im , f^2 supset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is injective but not surjective. However, some symmetry is lost in the assertion of the last part ("which is strict when $f$ is __ but not __"). In the first case I use the fact $ker f^n = ker f^n+1$ implies that $f$ is injective on $im , f^n = M$. In the second case I use the fact that $M supsetneq im , f$ would imply that $im , f^n supsetneq im , f^n+1$ because injective maps preserve strict inclusions.



My question is, is there a way to prove one of the statements in the appropriate category/framework such that the other follows from some kind of formulaic reversal of arrows? This is definitely more of a soft question because I'm not sure what this might mean, but the two situations seem symmetric enough that this might be plausible.










share|cite|improve this question













There are two statements which to me seem rather symmetric: Let $A$ be a ring, $M$ an $A$-module, and $f : M to M$.




If $M$ is Noetherian and $f$ is surjective, then $f$ is injective.



If $M$ is Artinian and $f$ is injective, then $f$ is surjective.




The proofs also seem symmetric in a sense: in the first case one constructs the increasing chain of ideals $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is surjective but not injective. In the second case one uses the injectivity of $f$ to construct the decreasing chain of ideals $M supset im , f supset im , f^2 supset dots$ which is strict when $f$ is injective but not surjective. However, some symmetry is lost in the assertion of the last part ("which is strict when $f$ is __ but not __"). In the first case I use the fact $ker f^n = ker f^n+1$ implies that $f$ is injective on $im , f^n = M$. In the second case I use the fact that $M supsetneq im , f$ would imply that $im , f^n supsetneq im , f^n+1$ because injective maps preserve strict inclusions.



My question is, is there a way to prove one of the statements in the appropriate category/framework such that the other follows from some kind of formulaic reversal of arrows? This is definitely more of a soft question because I'm not sure what this might mean, but the two situations seem symmetric enough that this might be plausible.







commutative-algebra category-theory






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked 2 hours ago









MCT

14.1k42564




14.1k42564











  • Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
    – user10354138
    1 hour ago











  • @user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
    – MCT
    58 mins ago
















  • Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
    – user10354138
    1 hour ago











  • @user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
    – MCT
    58 mins ago















Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
– user10354138
1 hour ago





Just prove one in R-mod and turn to the opposite category R-mod^op to get the dual?
– user10354138
1 hour ago













@user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
– MCT
58 mins ago




@user10354138 the opp isn't usually a category of modules so not sure why that works
– MCT
58 mins ago










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
3
down vote













Yes! These are both special cases of a general statement:




If $M$ is a Noetherian object in an abelian category and $f:Mto M$ is an epimorphism, then $f$ is a monomorphism.




Here an object is "Noetherian" if every ascending chain of subobjects stabilizes. The proof is exactly the same as in the case of modules: look at the ascending chain $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ (though it takes a little more work to prove this chain is strictly ascending in an abstract abelian category than in the case of modules).



Now, how does this imply the Artinian version? Well, the opposite category of $A$-modules is also an abelian category, so we can apply the result in that category. What does it mean for $M$ to be a Noetherian object in the opposite category of $A$-modules? Well, a subobject is a monomorphism $Nto M$ (up to isomorphism), which would be an epimorphism $Mto N$ in the original category. But such an epimorphism is determined (up to isomorphism) by its kernel, which is a subobject of $M$. So subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category are naturally in bijection with subobjects in the original category.



However, this bijection reverses the inclusion order on subobjects. Indeed, suppose $Nto M$ and $Pto M$ are two subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category, with $N$ contained in $P$. That means we can factor the map $Nto M$ as $Nto Pto M$. In the original category, then, this means we can factor the quotient map $Mto N$ as $Mto Pto N$. This is possible if and only if the kernel of $Mto N$ contains the kernel of $Mto P$. In other words, $N$ is contained in $P$ as subobjects in the opposite category iff the subobject in the original category corresponding to $P$ is contained in the subobject in the original category corresponding to $N$.



This means that $M$ is Noetherian in the opposite category iff $M$ is Artinian in the original category, since the order on subobjects has been reversed. Applying the result in the opposite category, we conclude that if $M$ is Artinian and if $f:Mto M$ is a monomorphism, then $f$ is an epimorphism.






share|cite|improve this answer
















  • 1




    Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
    – MCT
    1 hour ago

















up vote
2
down vote













If you look at the proof in the Noetherian case, you see that it
is valid in a general Abelian category. (A Noetherian object in an Abelian
category is one with ACC on subobjects). Now use the categorical
principle of duality. The opposite of an Abelian category is an Abelian
category, Noetherian becomes Artinian, injective becomes surjective etc.
So the Artinian case follows from the Noetherian case and vice versa.



Of course, algebra textbooks don't do this, largely because the opposite
of a module category is rarely also a module category.






share|cite|improve this answer




















    Your Answer




    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    );
    );
    , "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function()
    var channelOptions =
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    ;
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
    createEditor();
    );

    else
    createEditor();

    );

    function createEditor()
    StackExchange.prepareEditor(
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: false,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    );



    );













     

    draft saved


    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function ()
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2926782%2fcategorical-proof-of-a-seemingly-symmetric-statement-about-noetherian-artinian%23new-answer', 'question_page');

    );

    Post as a guest






























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes








    up vote
    3
    down vote













    Yes! These are both special cases of a general statement:




    If $M$ is a Noetherian object in an abelian category and $f:Mto M$ is an epimorphism, then $f$ is a monomorphism.




    Here an object is "Noetherian" if every ascending chain of subobjects stabilizes. The proof is exactly the same as in the case of modules: look at the ascending chain $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ (though it takes a little more work to prove this chain is strictly ascending in an abstract abelian category than in the case of modules).



    Now, how does this imply the Artinian version? Well, the opposite category of $A$-modules is also an abelian category, so we can apply the result in that category. What does it mean for $M$ to be a Noetherian object in the opposite category of $A$-modules? Well, a subobject is a monomorphism $Nto M$ (up to isomorphism), which would be an epimorphism $Mto N$ in the original category. But such an epimorphism is determined (up to isomorphism) by its kernel, which is a subobject of $M$. So subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category are naturally in bijection with subobjects in the original category.



    However, this bijection reverses the inclusion order on subobjects. Indeed, suppose $Nto M$ and $Pto M$ are two subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category, with $N$ contained in $P$. That means we can factor the map $Nto M$ as $Nto Pto M$. In the original category, then, this means we can factor the quotient map $Mto N$ as $Mto Pto N$. This is possible if and only if the kernel of $Mto N$ contains the kernel of $Mto P$. In other words, $N$ is contained in $P$ as subobjects in the opposite category iff the subobject in the original category corresponding to $P$ is contained in the subobject in the original category corresponding to $N$.



    This means that $M$ is Noetherian in the opposite category iff $M$ is Artinian in the original category, since the order on subobjects has been reversed. Applying the result in the opposite category, we conclude that if $M$ is Artinian and if $f:Mto M$ is a monomorphism, then $f$ is an epimorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer
















    • 1




      Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
      – MCT
      1 hour ago














    up vote
    3
    down vote













    Yes! These are both special cases of a general statement:




    If $M$ is a Noetherian object in an abelian category and $f:Mto M$ is an epimorphism, then $f$ is a monomorphism.




    Here an object is "Noetherian" if every ascending chain of subobjects stabilizes. The proof is exactly the same as in the case of modules: look at the ascending chain $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ (though it takes a little more work to prove this chain is strictly ascending in an abstract abelian category than in the case of modules).



    Now, how does this imply the Artinian version? Well, the opposite category of $A$-modules is also an abelian category, so we can apply the result in that category. What does it mean for $M$ to be a Noetherian object in the opposite category of $A$-modules? Well, a subobject is a monomorphism $Nto M$ (up to isomorphism), which would be an epimorphism $Mto N$ in the original category. But such an epimorphism is determined (up to isomorphism) by its kernel, which is a subobject of $M$. So subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category are naturally in bijection with subobjects in the original category.



    However, this bijection reverses the inclusion order on subobjects. Indeed, suppose $Nto M$ and $Pto M$ are two subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category, with $N$ contained in $P$. That means we can factor the map $Nto M$ as $Nto Pto M$. In the original category, then, this means we can factor the quotient map $Mto N$ as $Mto Pto N$. This is possible if and only if the kernel of $Mto N$ contains the kernel of $Mto P$. In other words, $N$ is contained in $P$ as subobjects in the opposite category iff the subobject in the original category corresponding to $P$ is contained in the subobject in the original category corresponding to $N$.



    This means that $M$ is Noetherian in the opposite category iff $M$ is Artinian in the original category, since the order on subobjects has been reversed. Applying the result in the opposite category, we conclude that if $M$ is Artinian and if $f:Mto M$ is a monomorphism, then $f$ is an epimorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer
















    • 1




      Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
      – MCT
      1 hour ago












    up vote
    3
    down vote










    up vote
    3
    down vote









    Yes! These are both special cases of a general statement:




    If $M$ is a Noetherian object in an abelian category and $f:Mto M$ is an epimorphism, then $f$ is a monomorphism.




    Here an object is "Noetherian" if every ascending chain of subobjects stabilizes. The proof is exactly the same as in the case of modules: look at the ascending chain $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ (though it takes a little more work to prove this chain is strictly ascending in an abstract abelian category than in the case of modules).



    Now, how does this imply the Artinian version? Well, the opposite category of $A$-modules is also an abelian category, so we can apply the result in that category. What does it mean for $M$ to be a Noetherian object in the opposite category of $A$-modules? Well, a subobject is a monomorphism $Nto M$ (up to isomorphism), which would be an epimorphism $Mto N$ in the original category. But such an epimorphism is determined (up to isomorphism) by its kernel, which is a subobject of $M$. So subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category are naturally in bijection with subobjects in the original category.



    However, this bijection reverses the inclusion order on subobjects. Indeed, suppose $Nto M$ and $Pto M$ are two subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category, with $N$ contained in $P$. That means we can factor the map $Nto M$ as $Nto Pto M$. In the original category, then, this means we can factor the quotient map $Mto N$ as $Mto Pto N$. This is possible if and only if the kernel of $Mto N$ contains the kernel of $Mto P$. In other words, $N$ is contained in $P$ as subobjects in the opposite category iff the subobject in the original category corresponding to $P$ is contained in the subobject in the original category corresponding to $N$.



    This means that $M$ is Noetherian in the opposite category iff $M$ is Artinian in the original category, since the order on subobjects has been reversed. Applying the result in the opposite category, we conclude that if $M$ is Artinian and if $f:Mto M$ is a monomorphism, then $f$ is an epimorphism.






    share|cite|improve this answer












    Yes! These are both special cases of a general statement:




    If $M$ is a Noetherian object in an abelian category and $f:Mto M$ is an epimorphism, then $f$ is a monomorphism.




    Here an object is "Noetherian" if every ascending chain of subobjects stabilizes. The proof is exactly the same as in the case of modules: look at the ascending chain $0 subset ker f subset ker f^2 subset dots$ (though it takes a little more work to prove this chain is strictly ascending in an abstract abelian category than in the case of modules).



    Now, how does this imply the Artinian version? Well, the opposite category of $A$-modules is also an abelian category, so we can apply the result in that category. What does it mean for $M$ to be a Noetherian object in the opposite category of $A$-modules? Well, a subobject is a monomorphism $Nto M$ (up to isomorphism), which would be an epimorphism $Mto N$ in the original category. But such an epimorphism is determined (up to isomorphism) by its kernel, which is a subobject of $M$. So subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category are naturally in bijection with subobjects in the original category.



    However, this bijection reverses the inclusion order on subobjects. Indeed, suppose $Nto M$ and $Pto M$ are two subobjects of $M$ in the opposite category, with $N$ contained in $P$. That means we can factor the map $Nto M$ as $Nto Pto M$. In the original category, then, this means we can factor the quotient map $Mto N$ as $Mto Pto N$. This is possible if and only if the kernel of $Mto N$ contains the kernel of $Mto P$. In other words, $N$ is contained in $P$ as subobjects in the opposite category iff the subobject in the original category corresponding to $P$ is contained in the subobject in the original category corresponding to $N$.



    This means that $M$ is Noetherian in the opposite category iff $M$ is Artinian in the original category, since the order on subobjects has been reversed. Applying the result in the opposite category, we conclude that if $M$ is Artinian and if $f:Mto M$ is a monomorphism, then $f$ is an epimorphism.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered 1 hour ago









    Eric Wofsey

    167k12196310




    167k12196310







    • 1




      Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
      – MCT
      1 hour ago












    • 1




      Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
      – MCT
      1 hour ago







    1




    1




    Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
    – MCT
    1 hour ago




    Great. As an aside, a reason I was not sure this construction existed is that the proof of both cases relied on looking at subobjects, when one case should be subs and the other case quotients. This is fixed by the viewpoint of looking at the cokernel instead of the image in the Artinian case, with chains being compositions of surjective maps in the other direction.
    – MCT
    1 hour ago










    up vote
    2
    down vote













    If you look at the proof in the Noetherian case, you see that it
    is valid in a general Abelian category. (A Noetherian object in an Abelian
    category is one with ACC on subobjects). Now use the categorical
    principle of duality. The opposite of an Abelian category is an Abelian
    category, Noetherian becomes Artinian, injective becomes surjective etc.
    So the Artinian case follows from the Noetherian case and vice versa.



    Of course, algebra textbooks don't do this, largely because the opposite
    of a module category is rarely also a module category.






    share|cite|improve this answer
























      up vote
      2
      down vote













      If you look at the proof in the Noetherian case, you see that it
      is valid in a general Abelian category. (A Noetherian object in an Abelian
      category is one with ACC on subobjects). Now use the categorical
      principle of duality. The opposite of an Abelian category is an Abelian
      category, Noetherian becomes Artinian, injective becomes surjective etc.
      So the Artinian case follows from the Noetherian case and vice versa.



      Of course, algebra textbooks don't do this, largely because the opposite
      of a module category is rarely also a module category.






      share|cite|improve this answer






















        up vote
        2
        down vote










        up vote
        2
        down vote









        If you look at the proof in the Noetherian case, you see that it
        is valid in a general Abelian category. (A Noetherian object in an Abelian
        category is one with ACC on subobjects). Now use the categorical
        principle of duality. The opposite of an Abelian category is an Abelian
        category, Noetherian becomes Artinian, injective becomes surjective etc.
        So the Artinian case follows from the Noetherian case and vice versa.



        Of course, algebra textbooks don't do this, largely because the opposite
        of a module category is rarely also a module category.






        share|cite|improve this answer












        If you look at the proof in the Noetherian case, you see that it
        is valid in a general Abelian category. (A Noetherian object in an Abelian
        category is one with ACC on subobjects). Now use the categorical
        principle of duality. The opposite of an Abelian category is an Abelian
        category, Noetherian becomes Artinian, injective becomes surjective etc.
        So the Artinian case follows from the Noetherian case and vice versa.



        Of course, algebra textbooks don't do this, largely because the opposite
        of a module category is rarely also a module category.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered 1 hour ago









        Lord Shark the Unknown

        90.2k955117




        90.2k955117



























             

            draft saved


            draft discarded















































             


            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f2926782%2fcategorical-proof-of-a-seemingly-symmetric-statement-about-noetherian-artinian%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest













































































            Comments

            Popular posts from this blog

            Long meetings (6-7 hours a day): Being “babysat” by supervisor

            Is the Concept of Multiple Fantasy Races Scientifically Flawed? [closed]

            Confectionery