Why is Lebesgue measure theory asymmetric?

The name of the pictureThe name of the pictureThe name of the pictureClash Royale CLAN TAG#URR8PPP











up vote
17
down vote

favorite
6












A set $Esubseteq mathbbR^d$ is said to be Jordan measurable if its inner measure $m_*(E)$ and outer measure $m^*(E)$ are equal.However, Lebesgue mesure theory is developed with only outer measure.



A function is Riemann integrable iff its upper integral and lower integral are equal.However, in Lebesgue integration theory, we rarely use upper Lebesgue integral.



Why are outer measure and lower integral more important than inner measure and upper integral?







share|cite|improve this question


















  • 9




    Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
    – Noah Schweber
    Aug 22 at 2:41







  • 3




    I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
    – Praphulla Koushik
    Aug 22 at 2:55







  • 4




    I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 8:52






  • 2




    Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 9:25














up vote
17
down vote

favorite
6












A set $Esubseteq mathbbR^d$ is said to be Jordan measurable if its inner measure $m_*(E)$ and outer measure $m^*(E)$ are equal.However, Lebesgue mesure theory is developed with only outer measure.



A function is Riemann integrable iff its upper integral and lower integral are equal.However, in Lebesgue integration theory, we rarely use upper Lebesgue integral.



Why are outer measure and lower integral more important than inner measure and upper integral?







share|cite|improve this question


















  • 9




    Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
    – Noah Schweber
    Aug 22 at 2:41







  • 3




    I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
    – Praphulla Koushik
    Aug 22 at 2:55







  • 4




    I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 8:52






  • 2




    Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 9:25












up vote
17
down vote

favorite
6









up vote
17
down vote

favorite
6






6





A set $Esubseteq mathbbR^d$ is said to be Jordan measurable if its inner measure $m_*(E)$ and outer measure $m^*(E)$ are equal.However, Lebesgue mesure theory is developed with only outer measure.



A function is Riemann integrable iff its upper integral and lower integral are equal.However, in Lebesgue integration theory, we rarely use upper Lebesgue integral.



Why are outer measure and lower integral more important than inner measure and upper integral?







share|cite|improve this question














A set $Esubseteq mathbbR^d$ is said to be Jordan measurable if its inner measure $m_*(E)$ and outer measure $m^*(E)$ are equal.However, Lebesgue mesure theory is developed with only outer measure.



A function is Riemann integrable iff its upper integral and lower integral are equal.However, in Lebesgue integration theory, we rarely use upper Lebesgue integral.



Why are outer measure and lower integral more important than inner measure and upper integral?









share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Aug 22 at 14:36

























asked Aug 22 at 0:15









satoukibi

915




915







  • 9




    Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
    – Noah Schweber
    Aug 22 at 2:41







  • 3




    I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
    – Praphulla Koushik
    Aug 22 at 2:55







  • 4




    I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 8:52






  • 2




    Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 9:25












  • 9




    Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
    – Noah Schweber
    Aug 22 at 2:41







  • 3




    I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
    – Praphulla Koushik
    Aug 22 at 2:55







  • 4




    I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 8:52






  • 2




    Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
    – Francois Ziegler
    Aug 22 at 9:25







9




9




Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
– Noah Schweber
Aug 22 at 2:41





Lebesgue measurability can also be defined via inner and outer measure, and I believe that was how it was originally defined, the "outer measure only" definition by Caratheodory coming later. That said, I can't speak to why the Caratheodory definition seems to be presented more frequently.
– Noah Schweber
Aug 22 at 2:41





3




3




I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
– Praphulla Koushik
Aug 22 at 2:55





I do not think it is asymetric.. It may be true that for a set $Esubseteq mathbbR$, lebesgue outer measure is defined by covering it from out side by open intervals... But, you call a set $E$ Lebesgue measurable only if for any $Asubseteq mathbbR$ you have $mu(A)=mu(Acap E)+mu(Acap E^c)$.. This can be seen as taking care of outer approximation (in case when you consider $Acap E$) and inner approximation (when you consider $Acap E^C$).. Does it make some sense.. ?? It is vague but I can not make it any better :D
– Praphulla Koushik
Aug 22 at 2:55





4




4




I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
– Francois Ziegler
Aug 22 at 8:52




I agree with Noah and Praphulla — it’s rather an expository choice. As further evidence, see e.g. Bourbaki, Chap. IV, §4, exercises 6b) and 7b) or Godement (1948, p. 4, fourth displayed equation).
– Francois Ziegler
Aug 22 at 8:52




2




2




Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
– Francois Ziegler
Aug 22 at 9:25




Also “Historical note” in Chap. V, pp. 126–127: In Lebesgue’s thesis, “imitating the Peano–Jordan method, the ‘outer measure’ of a bounded set $Asubsetmathbf R$ is defined... then, if $I$ is an interval containing $A$, the ‘inner measure’ of $A$ is the difference of the outer measures of $I$ and $I - A$; one thus obtains a notion of ‘measurable set’...”
– Francois Ziegler
Aug 22 at 9:25










5 Answers
5






active

oldest

votes

















up vote
15
down vote



accepted










I have a (possibly idiosyncratic) view that the natural form of measure theory is for finite measure spaces and bounded functions. Other cases are obviously very important, but we have to work harder to get them. You can see this is many of the proofs, where the finite case is easier, and we have to work a bit more to generalize it. For example, the usual proof of the Radon-Nikodym theorem works that way.



In the finite measure space case, with bounded functions, everything can be made symmetric. The symmetry is broken in the general case, because allowing infinity breaks it. In integration, this asymmetry shows up in the way we have to have separate theorems for the non-negative measurable functions and the integrable functions. For bounded functions on finite measure spaces you don't need to impose any extra conditions.






share|cite|improve this answer
















  • 5




    One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
    – Terry Tao
    Aug 22 at 14:56







  • 5




    If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
    – Terry Tao
    Aug 22 at 15:03


















up vote
10
down vote













I think your statement about Jordan is actually wrong. If $m_*(E) = infty$ and $m^*(E) = infty$, then $E$ need not be Jordan measurable. If you talk only about bounded sets $E$, then your characterization is correct. But it is also correct for Lebesgue measure (using Lebesgue inner and outer measure).



The reason for Caratheodory's criterion is to define measurability when even bounded sets could have infinite measure, so that restricting to bounded sets no longer helps. One of Caratheorory's examples was an "arc length" measure for sets in $mathbb R^n$. In that case, there is no obvious way to define inner measure. But we still can define outer measure. And then we need a criterion for measurability that uses only outer measure.



More recent mathematicians have developed a way to start only with an "inner measure" and go from there.






share|cite|improve this answer



























    up vote
    6
    down vote













    I think, the reason is that if the ground space has infinite measure, you can not define the measurable sets as those for which inner measure equals the outer measure: it may happen that both are infinite, while the set is still not measurable.



    Note also (this may be related) that outer and inner regarity behave differently in general. For example, the sigma-finite Borel measure on the Polish space is inner regular, but not always outer regular (example: counting measure of rational numbers as a measure on $mathbbR$.)






    share|cite|improve this answer



























      up vote
      1
      down vote













      Concerning Tao comment that the symmetry is broken by declaring 0⋅∞ = ∞⋅0 = 0, I would like to add that this is the reason why Lebesgue integral does not satisfy Newton-Leibniz formula. Namely, for Cantor-Lebesgue function f, f(1)–f(0) = 1 but ∫01f’ = 0 because f’ = ∞ on Cantor set C which has measure 0 (and f’ = 0 on its complement). But if we realize that the measure of C is 0 = (1, 2/3, 4/9, ... ) and f’ = ∞ = (1, 3/2, 9/4, ...) then we see that this particular 0⋅∞ is not 0 but exactly 1, as it should be by Newton-Leibniz formula. We have the similar problem with countable additivity of limiting frequencies, which is usually contradicted by an infinite lottery with tokens 1,2,3,4,…. This contradiction also depends on ∞⋅0 = 0 and disappears if we really calculate the relevant ∞⋅0 ( https://www.fsb.unizg.hr/matematika/download/ZS/clanci/ZS-a_note_on_probability_frequency.pdf )






      share|cite|improve this answer



























        up vote
        0
        down vote













        My two cents. Outer measures are sub-additive on countable coverings: $$Asubset cup _jinmathbbN A_jquad Rightarrow quad mu( A)le sum_jinmathbbNmu(A_j)$$
        which is somehow a nicer and more practical property than the analogous dual property of super-additivity for inner measures (even in the case of finite measures). It gives a bound on the set $A$ in terms of the supposedly simpler sets $A_j$. Also, we like sub-additivity more than super-additivity, because it recalls norms.






        share|cite|improve this answer




















          Your Answer




          StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function ()
          return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function ()
          StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix)
          StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
          );
          );
          , "mathjax-editing");

          StackExchange.ready(function()
          var channelOptions =
          tags: "".split(" "),
          id: "504"
          ;
          initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

          StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
          // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
          if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
          StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
          createEditor();
          );

          else
          createEditor();

          );

          function createEditor()
          StackExchange.prepareEditor(
          heartbeatType: 'answer',
          convertImagesToLinks: true,
          noModals: false,
          showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
          reputationToPostImages: 10,
          bindNavPrevention: true,
          postfix: "",
          noCode: true, onDemand: true,
          discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
          ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
          );



          );













           

          draft saved


          draft discarded


















          StackExchange.ready(
          function ()
          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f308856%2fwhy-is-lebesgue-measure-theory-asymmetric%23new-answer', 'question_page');

          );

          Post as a guest






























          5 Answers
          5






          active

          oldest

          votes








          5 Answers
          5






          active

          oldest

          votes









          active

          oldest

          votes






          active

          oldest

          votes








          up vote
          15
          down vote



          accepted










          I have a (possibly idiosyncratic) view that the natural form of measure theory is for finite measure spaces and bounded functions. Other cases are obviously very important, but we have to work harder to get them. You can see this is many of the proofs, where the finite case is easier, and we have to work a bit more to generalize it. For example, the usual proof of the Radon-Nikodym theorem works that way.



          In the finite measure space case, with bounded functions, everything can be made symmetric. The symmetry is broken in the general case, because allowing infinity breaks it. In integration, this asymmetry shows up in the way we have to have separate theorems for the non-negative measurable functions and the integrable functions. For bounded functions on finite measure spaces you don't need to impose any extra conditions.






          share|cite|improve this answer
















          • 5




            One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 14:56







          • 5




            If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 15:03















          up vote
          15
          down vote



          accepted










          I have a (possibly idiosyncratic) view that the natural form of measure theory is for finite measure spaces and bounded functions. Other cases are obviously very important, but we have to work harder to get them. You can see this is many of the proofs, where the finite case is easier, and we have to work a bit more to generalize it. For example, the usual proof of the Radon-Nikodym theorem works that way.



          In the finite measure space case, with bounded functions, everything can be made symmetric. The symmetry is broken in the general case, because allowing infinity breaks it. In integration, this asymmetry shows up in the way we have to have separate theorems for the non-negative measurable functions and the integrable functions. For bounded functions on finite measure spaces you don't need to impose any extra conditions.






          share|cite|improve this answer
















          • 5




            One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 14:56







          • 5




            If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 15:03













          up vote
          15
          down vote



          accepted







          up vote
          15
          down vote



          accepted






          I have a (possibly idiosyncratic) view that the natural form of measure theory is for finite measure spaces and bounded functions. Other cases are obviously very important, but we have to work harder to get them. You can see this is many of the proofs, where the finite case is easier, and we have to work a bit more to generalize it. For example, the usual proof of the Radon-Nikodym theorem works that way.



          In the finite measure space case, with bounded functions, everything can be made symmetric. The symmetry is broken in the general case, because allowing infinity breaks it. In integration, this asymmetry shows up in the way we have to have separate theorems for the non-negative measurable functions and the integrable functions. For bounded functions on finite measure spaces you don't need to impose any extra conditions.






          share|cite|improve this answer












          I have a (possibly idiosyncratic) view that the natural form of measure theory is for finite measure spaces and bounded functions. Other cases are obviously very important, but we have to work harder to get them. You can see this is many of the proofs, where the finite case is easier, and we have to work a bit more to generalize it. For example, the usual proof of the Radon-Nikodym theorem works that way.



          In the finite measure space case, with bounded functions, everything can be made symmetric. The symmetry is broken in the general case, because allowing infinity breaks it. In integration, this asymmetry shows up in the way we have to have separate theorems for the non-negative measurable functions and the integrable functions. For bounded functions on finite measure spaces you don't need to impose any extra conditions.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Aug 22 at 9:26









          arsmath

          4,19412340




          4,19412340







          • 5




            One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 14:56







          • 5




            If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 15:03













          • 5




            One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 14:56







          • 5




            If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
            – Terry Tao
            Aug 22 at 15:03








          5




          5




          One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
          – Terry Tao
          Aug 22 at 14:56





          One very explicit way in which the symmetry is broken is by declaring $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0$ to equal $0$ rather than $infty$. On the non-negative extended reals $[0,+infty]$, this makes multiplication continuous from below, but not from above: if $a_n,b_n in [0,+infty]$ increase to $a,b$ respectively, then $a_n b_n$ increases to $ab$, but the same is not true for decreasing sequences. I think this already explains much of the asymmetry in Lebesgue measure theory.
          – Terry Tao
          Aug 22 at 14:56





          5




          5




          If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
          – Terry Tao
          Aug 22 at 15:03





          If one adopted the opposite convention $0 cdot infty = infty cdot 0 = infty$, and reversed the roles of upper and lower integrals, I think one also gets a self-consistent theory, but one that is completely degenerate as soon as one allows $infty$ as a possible value of a function or as a possible value of a measure: all integrals would be infinite or divergent, because all functions are infinite on the empty set.
          – Terry Tao
          Aug 22 at 15:03











          up vote
          10
          down vote













          I think your statement about Jordan is actually wrong. If $m_*(E) = infty$ and $m^*(E) = infty$, then $E$ need not be Jordan measurable. If you talk only about bounded sets $E$, then your characterization is correct. But it is also correct for Lebesgue measure (using Lebesgue inner and outer measure).



          The reason for Caratheodory's criterion is to define measurability when even bounded sets could have infinite measure, so that restricting to bounded sets no longer helps. One of Caratheorory's examples was an "arc length" measure for sets in $mathbb R^n$. In that case, there is no obvious way to define inner measure. But we still can define outer measure. And then we need a criterion for measurability that uses only outer measure.



          More recent mathematicians have developed a way to start only with an "inner measure" and go from there.






          share|cite|improve this answer
























            up vote
            10
            down vote













            I think your statement about Jordan is actually wrong. If $m_*(E) = infty$ and $m^*(E) = infty$, then $E$ need not be Jordan measurable. If you talk only about bounded sets $E$, then your characterization is correct. But it is also correct for Lebesgue measure (using Lebesgue inner and outer measure).



            The reason for Caratheodory's criterion is to define measurability when even bounded sets could have infinite measure, so that restricting to bounded sets no longer helps. One of Caratheorory's examples was an "arc length" measure for sets in $mathbb R^n$. In that case, there is no obvious way to define inner measure. But we still can define outer measure. And then we need a criterion for measurability that uses only outer measure.



            More recent mathematicians have developed a way to start only with an "inner measure" and go from there.






            share|cite|improve this answer






















              up vote
              10
              down vote










              up vote
              10
              down vote









              I think your statement about Jordan is actually wrong. If $m_*(E) = infty$ and $m^*(E) = infty$, then $E$ need not be Jordan measurable. If you talk only about bounded sets $E$, then your characterization is correct. But it is also correct for Lebesgue measure (using Lebesgue inner and outer measure).



              The reason for Caratheodory's criterion is to define measurability when even bounded sets could have infinite measure, so that restricting to bounded sets no longer helps. One of Caratheorory's examples was an "arc length" measure for sets in $mathbb R^n$. In that case, there is no obvious way to define inner measure. But we still can define outer measure. And then we need a criterion for measurability that uses only outer measure.



              More recent mathematicians have developed a way to start only with an "inner measure" and go from there.






              share|cite|improve this answer












              I think your statement about Jordan is actually wrong. If $m_*(E) = infty$ and $m^*(E) = infty$, then $E$ need not be Jordan measurable. If you talk only about bounded sets $E$, then your characterization is correct. But it is also correct for Lebesgue measure (using Lebesgue inner and outer measure).



              The reason for Caratheodory's criterion is to define measurability when even bounded sets could have infinite measure, so that restricting to bounded sets no longer helps. One of Caratheorory's examples was an "arc length" measure for sets in $mathbb R^n$. In that case, there is no obvious way to define inner measure. But we still can define outer measure. And then we need a criterion for measurability that uses only outer measure.



              More recent mathematicians have developed a way to start only with an "inner measure" and go from there.







              share|cite|improve this answer












              share|cite|improve this answer



              share|cite|improve this answer










              answered Aug 22 at 12:57









              Gerald Edgar

              27k269153




              27k269153




















                  up vote
                  6
                  down vote













                  I think, the reason is that if the ground space has infinite measure, you can not define the measurable sets as those for which inner measure equals the outer measure: it may happen that both are infinite, while the set is still not measurable.



                  Note also (this may be related) that outer and inner regarity behave differently in general. For example, the sigma-finite Borel measure on the Polish space is inner regular, but not always outer regular (example: counting measure of rational numbers as a measure on $mathbbR$.)






                  share|cite|improve this answer
























                    up vote
                    6
                    down vote













                    I think, the reason is that if the ground space has infinite measure, you can not define the measurable sets as those for which inner measure equals the outer measure: it may happen that both are infinite, while the set is still not measurable.



                    Note also (this may be related) that outer and inner regarity behave differently in general. For example, the sigma-finite Borel measure on the Polish space is inner regular, but not always outer regular (example: counting measure of rational numbers as a measure on $mathbbR$.)






                    share|cite|improve this answer






















                      up vote
                      6
                      down vote










                      up vote
                      6
                      down vote









                      I think, the reason is that if the ground space has infinite measure, you can not define the measurable sets as those for which inner measure equals the outer measure: it may happen that both are infinite, while the set is still not measurable.



                      Note also (this may be related) that outer and inner regarity behave differently in general. For example, the sigma-finite Borel measure on the Polish space is inner regular, but not always outer regular (example: counting measure of rational numbers as a measure on $mathbbR$.)






                      share|cite|improve this answer












                      I think, the reason is that if the ground space has infinite measure, you can not define the measurable sets as those for which inner measure equals the outer measure: it may happen that both are infinite, while the set is still not measurable.



                      Note also (this may be related) that outer and inner regarity behave differently in general. For example, the sigma-finite Borel measure on the Polish space is inner regular, but not always outer regular (example: counting measure of rational numbers as a measure on $mathbbR$.)







                      share|cite|improve this answer












                      share|cite|improve this answer



                      share|cite|improve this answer










                      answered Aug 22 at 7:17









                      Fedor Petrov

                      44.6k5107211




                      44.6k5107211




















                          up vote
                          1
                          down vote













                          Concerning Tao comment that the symmetry is broken by declaring 0⋅∞ = ∞⋅0 = 0, I would like to add that this is the reason why Lebesgue integral does not satisfy Newton-Leibniz formula. Namely, for Cantor-Lebesgue function f, f(1)–f(0) = 1 but ∫01f’ = 0 because f’ = ∞ on Cantor set C which has measure 0 (and f’ = 0 on its complement). But if we realize that the measure of C is 0 = (1, 2/3, 4/9, ... ) and f’ = ∞ = (1, 3/2, 9/4, ...) then we see that this particular 0⋅∞ is not 0 but exactly 1, as it should be by Newton-Leibniz formula. We have the similar problem with countable additivity of limiting frequencies, which is usually contradicted by an infinite lottery with tokens 1,2,3,4,…. This contradiction also depends on ∞⋅0 = 0 and disappears if we really calculate the relevant ∞⋅0 ( https://www.fsb.unizg.hr/matematika/download/ZS/clanci/ZS-a_note_on_probability_frequency.pdf )






                          share|cite|improve this answer
























                            up vote
                            1
                            down vote













                            Concerning Tao comment that the symmetry is broken by declaring 0⋅∞ = ∞⋅0 = 0, I would like to add that this is the reason why Lebesgue integral does not satisfy Newton-Leibniz formula. Namely, for Cantor-Lebesgue function f, f(1)–f(0) = 1 but ∫01f’ = 0 because f’ = ∞ on Cantor set C which has measure 0 (and f’ = 0 on its complement). But if we realize that the measure of C is 0 = (1, 2/3, 4/9, ... ) and f’ = ∞ = (1, 3/2, 9/4, ...) then we see that this particular 0⋅∞ is not 0 but exactly 1, as it should be by Newton-Leibniz formula. We have the similar problem with countable additivity of limiting frequencies, which is usually contradicted by an infinite lottery with tokens 1,2,3,4,…. This contradiction also depends on ∞⋅0 = 0 and disappears if we really calculate the relevant ∞⋅0 ( https://www.fsb.unizg.hr/matematika/download/ZS/clanci/ZS-a_note_on_probability_frequency.pdf )






                            share|cite|improve this answer






















                              up vote
                              1
                              down vote










                              up vote
                              1
                              down vote









                              Concerning Tao comment that the symmetry is broken by declaring 0⋅∞ = ∞⋅0 = 0, I would like to add that this is the reason why Lebesgue integral does not satisfy Newton-Leibniz formula. Namely, for Cantor-Lebesgue function f, f(1)–f(0) = 1 but ∫01f’ = 0 because f’ = ∞ on Cantor set C which has measure 0 (and f’ = 0 on its complement). But if we realize that the measure of C is 0 = (1, 2/3, 4/9, ... ) and f’ = ∞ = (1, 3/2, 9/4, ...) then we see that this particular 0⋅∞ is not 0 but exactly 1, as it should be by Newton-Leibniz formula. We have the similar problem with countable additivity of limiting frequencies, which is usually contradicted by an infinite lottery with tokens 1,2,3,4,…. This contradiction also depends on ∞⋅0 = 0 and disappears if we really calculate the relevant ∞⋅0 ( https://www.fsb.unizg.hr/matematika/download/ZS/clanci/ZS-a_note_on_probability_frequency.pdf )






                              share|cite|improve this answer












                              Concerning Tao comment that the symmetry is broken by declaring 0⋅∞ = ∞⋅0 = 0, I would like to add that this is the reason why Lebesgue integral does not satisfy Newton-Leibniz formula. Namely, for Cantor-Lebesgue function f, f(1)–f(0) = 1 but ∫01f’ = 0 because f’ = ∞ on Cantor set C which has measure 0 (and f’ = 0 on its complement). But if we realize that the measure of C is 0 = (1, 2/3, 4/9, ... ) and f’ = ∞ = (1, 3/2, 9/4, ...) then we see that this particular 0⋅∞ is not 0 but exactly 1, as it should be by Newton-Leibniz formula. We have the similar problem with countable additivity of limiting frequencies, which is usually contradicted by an infinite lottery with tokens 1,2,3,4,…. This contradiction also depends on ∞⋅0 = 0 and disappears if we really calculate the relevant ∞⋅0 ( https://www.fsb.unizg.hr/matematika/download/ZS/clanci/ZS-a_note_on_probability_frequency.pdf )







                              share|cite|improve this answer












                              share|cite|improve this answer



                              share|cite|improve this answer










                              answered Aug 28 at 18:05









                              Zvonimir Sikic

                              111




                              111




















                                  up vote
                                  0
                                  down vote













                                  My two cents. Outer measures are sub-additive on countable coverings: $$Asubset cup _jinmathbbN A_jquad Rightarrow quad mu( A)le sum_jinmathbbNmu(A_j)$$
                                  which is somehow a nicer and more practical property than the analogous dual property of super-additivity for inner measures (even in the case of finite measures). It gives a bound on the set $A$ in terms of the supposedly simpler sets $A_j$. Also, we like sub-additivity more than super-additivity, because it recalls norms.






                                  share|cite|improve this answer
























                                    up vote
                                    0
                                    down vote













                                    My two cents. Outer measures are sub-additive on countable coverings: $$Asubset cup _jinmathbbN A_jquad Rightarrow quad mu( A)le sum_jinmathbbNmu(A_j)$$
                                    which is somehow a nicer and more practical property than the analogous dual property of super-additivity for inner measures (even in the case of finite measures). It gives a bound on the set $A$ in terms of the supposedly simpler sets $A_j$. Also, we like sub-additivity more than super-additivity, because it recalls norms.






                                    share|cite|improve this answer






















                                      up vote
                                      0
                                      down vote










                                      up vote
                                      0
                                      down vote









                                      My two cents. Outer measures are sub-additive on countable coverings: $$Asubset cup _jinmathbbN A_jquad Rightarrow quad mu( A)le sum_jinmathbbNmu(A_j)$$
                                      which is somehow a nicer and more practical property than the analogous dual property of super-additivity for inner measures (even in the case of finite measures). It gives a bound on the set $A$ in terms of the supposedly simpler sets $A_j$. Also, we like sub-additivity more than super-additivity, because it recalls norms.






                                      share|cite|improve this answer












                                      My two cents. Outer measures are sub-additive on countable coverings: $$Asubset cup _jinmathbbN A_jquad Rightarrow quad mu( A)le sum_jinmathbbNmu(A_j)$$
                                      which is somehow a nicer and more practical property than the analogous dual property of super-additivity for inner measures (even in the case of finite measures). It gives a bound on the set $A$ in terms of the supposedly simpler sets $A_j$. Also, we like sub-additivity more than super-additivity, because it recalls norms.







                                      share|cite|improve this answer












                                      share|cite|improve this answer



                                      share|cite|improve this answer










                                      answered Aug 28 at 19:50









                                      Pietro Majer

                                      37.9k277180




                                      37.9k277180



























                                           

                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded















































                                           


                                          draft saved


                                          draft discarded














                                          StackExchange.ready(
                                          function ()
                                          StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmathoverflow.net%2fquestions%2f308856%2fwhy-is-lebesgue-measure-theory-asymmetric%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                                          );

                                          Post as a guest













































































                                          Comments

                                          Popular posts from this blog

                                          Long meetings (6-7 hours a day): Being “babysat” by supervisor

                                          Is the Concept of Multiple Fantasy Races Scientifically Flawed? [closed]

                                          Confectionery